Epistemology of Testimony

Paul Faulkner
Table of contents

The epistemology of testimony starts with our finding utterances, in the broad Gricean sense, intelligible. A straight assertion is a piece of testimony, but so too is something speaker meant, or a proposition communicated by a map or road sign. Testimony is any intelligible utterance whose acceptance by its recipient could be the acquisition of belief. And ‘testimony’ refers to that way of acquiring belief which is the acceptance of intelligibly presented content. This way of forming belief is fundamental to our cognitive lives. It is fundamental in that testimonial beliefs permeate every aspect of our cognitive life. Is the belief that this tree is an oak perceptual or testimonial? And it is fundamental in that if testimonial beliefs are not accorded the status of knowledge or regarded as warranted, then the consequence is a form of scepticism. We would not know much about history or geography. We would know little about the content of other minds. Science would not be recognised as a body of knowledge. We would not know the identity of our parents. So the second starting point in giving an epistemological theory of testimony is the presumption that the acceptance of testimony is not merely a way of acquiring belief, it is also a way of acquiring warranted belief and knowledge. The question is then, how is this the case?

Full-text access is restricted to subscribers. Log in to obtain additional credentials. For subscription information see Subscription & Price.

References

Burge, T.
1993 “Content Preservation”. Philosophical Review 102(4): 457–488. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Coady, C.A.J.
1992Testimony: A Philosophical Study. First ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Google Scholar
Dummett, M.
1993 “Testimony and Memory,”. In The Seas of Language, edited by M. Dummett, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Google Scholar
Faulkner, Paul.
2011Knowledge on trust. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Fricker, E.
1995 “Telling and Trusting: Reductionism and Anti-Reductionism in the Epistemology of Testimony”. MIND 104(414): 393–411. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Goldberg, Sanford.
2007Anti-Individualism: Mind and Language, Knowledge and Justification. Cambridge: CUP. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Grice, P.
1957 “Meaning”. In Studies in the Way of Words, edited by P. Grice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. DOI logo  BoPGoogle Scholar
Lackey, Jennifer
2008Learning from Words – Testimony as a Source of Knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Lackey, Jennifer, and Ernest Sosa
eds. 2006The Epistemology of Testimony. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Matilal, B.K., and A. Chakrabarti,
eds. 1994Knowing From Words- Western and Indian Philosophical Analysis of Understanding and Testimony. Edited by J. Hintikka. Vol. 230, Studies in Epistemology. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Mcdowell, J.
1994 “Knowledge by Hearsay”. In Meaning, Knowledge and Reality, edited by J. Mcdowell. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Moran, R.
2005a “Getting Told and Being Believed”. Philosophers’ Imprint 5(5): 1–29. Google Scholar
2005b “The Problems of Sincerity”. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 105(3): 341–61. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Shapin, S.
1994A Social History of Truth: Civility and Science in Seventeenth Century England. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Google Scholar
Williams, B.
2002Truth and Truthfulness. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Google Scholar