Modal logic

Paul Gochet

Table of contents

Standard elementary logic studies the deductive inferences which rest on two sets of logical constants: the connectives ‘not’, ‘and’, ‘either … or …’, ‘if … then …’ and the quantifiers ‘all’ and ‘some’. Modal logic extends the logical lexicon in order to account for the validity or non-validity of inferences which depends on the presence of modal terms such as ‘necessarily’ or ‘possibly’. With respect to arguments involving these terms, intuition cannot be trusted. Even the best logicians and philosophers fall prey to fallacies in this area. For instance, Etchemendy (1990: 87) discovered a hidden fallacious move in Tarski's account of logical consequence, where he went from a statement of the form ‘Necessarily if p and q, then not r’ to a statement of the form ‘if p then necessarily if q then not r’.

Full-text access is restricted to subscribers. Log in to obtain additional credentials. For subscription information see Subscription & Price.

References

Ackrill, J.L.
(ed.) 1963Aristotle's Categories and De interpretatione. Oxford University Press. Google Scholar
Aristotle
: see Ackrill (ed.) 1963 and Ross (ed.) 1928 Google Scholar
Barcan Marcus, R.
1946A functional calculus of first order based on strict implication. The Journal of Symbolic Logic 11: 1–17. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Bar-Hillel, Y.
1970Aspects of Language. North Holland.  BoPGoogle Scholar
1971Pragmatics of natural languages. Reidel.  BoPGoogle Scholar
Blackburn, P., M. De Rijke & Y. Venema
2001Modal Logic. Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Van Benthem, J.
1977Tense logic and standard logic. Logique et Analyse 80: 395–437. Google Scholar
1983The Logic of Time. A Model-Theoretic Investigation into the Varieties of Temporal Ontology and Temporal Discourse. Reidel. Google Scholar
Carnap, R.
1946Modalities and Quantification. The Journal of Symbolic Logic 11: 33–64. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
1963Carnap's Intellectual autobiography. In P.A. Schilpp (ed.) The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. Open Court. Google Scholar
Fitting, M. & R. Mendelsohn
1998First-Order Modal Logic. Kluwer. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Gabbay, D.
1974Tense Logic and the Tenses of English. In J. Moravcsik (ed.) Logic and Philosophy for Linguists: 177–186. Mouton. Google Scholar
1976Investigations in modal and tense logics. With applications to Problems in Philosophy and Linguistics. Reidel. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Gabbay, D. & J. Woods
(eds.) 2006The Handbook of History of Logic, vol. 7 Logic and the Modalities in the Twentieth Century. Elsevier. Google Scholar
Garson, J.
2006Modal Logic for Philosophers. Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Goranko, V.
1996Hierarchies of Modal and Temporal Logic with Reference. The Journal of Logic, Language and Information 5: 1–24. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Hughes, G.E. & M.J. Cresswell
1996A new introduction to modal logic. Methuen. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Kamp, H
1971Formal Properties of ‘Now’. Theoria 37: 227–273. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Lewis, I. & C.H. Langford
(1959) [1932]Symbolic logic. Dover. Google Scholar
Lyons, J.
1977Semantics, vol. 2. Cambridge University Press.  BoPGoogle Scholar
Mctaggart, J.M.E.
1908The Unreality of Time. Mind: 457–474. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Moisil, G.
1972Essai sur les logiques non chrysipiennes. Académie Socialiste de Roumanie. Google Scholar
Palmer, F.R
1979Modality and the English modals. Longman.  BoPGoogle Scholar
Reichenbach, H.
(1974) [1947]Analysis of Conversational Language. In J. Moravcsik (ed.) Logic and Philosophy for Linguists: 122–141. Mouton. Google Scholar
Ross, W.D.
(ed.) 1928The works of Aristotle: Analytica Priora. Clarendon. Google Scholar
Scott, D.
1971On engendering an illusion of understanding. Journal of Philosophy 68(21): 787–807. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Wolper, P.
1983Temporal Logic Can Be More Expressive. Information and Control 56: 72–99. DOI logoGoogle Scholar