Truth-conditional pragmatics

Jacques Moeschler
Table of contents

Pragmatics has been oriented, from its philosophical origins (Austin 1962; Grice 1975), in a direction which has made truth-conditional meaning either part of the semantic meaning (Gazdar 1979), or placed it outside the scope of pragmatics. Austin convincingly argued against the “descriptive illusion,” proposing an analysis of the classical philosophical description of meaning (sense and reference) as “the act of ‘saying something’,” corresponding to what he calls the locutionary act (Austin 1962: 94), whereas the main meaning component of an utterance would be captured by the illocutionary act. Gazdar, an emblematic defender of a formal approach to pragmatics, popularized its scope by means of his famous equation: “pragmatics = meaning – truth conditions” (Gazdar 1979: 2). This general agreement about the exclusion of truth-conditional meaning from the scope of pragmatics has been accepted as a common assumption of the developments of pragmatics following Grice (Gazdar 1979; Horn 1984, 1989), with as its main domain of investigation implicatures, and more specifically generalized conversational implicatures, even if things are less straightforward when we look at Levinson’s (2000) approach to generalized conversational implicatures, as discussed in Huang (2014).

Full-text access is restricted to subscribers. Log in to obtain additional credentials. For subscription information see Subscription & Price.

References

Austin, John L.
1962How to Do Things with Words. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Blakemore, Diane
1987Semantic Constraints on Relevance. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Blochowiak, Joanna
2010 “Some formal properties of causal and inferential ‘because’ in different embedding contexts.” Generative Grammar@Geneva 6: 191–202.Google Scholar
2014a “A presuppositional account of causal and temporal interpretations of and.” Topoi. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2014b. A Theoretical Approach to the Quest for Understanding. Semantics and Pragmatics of whys and becauses. PhD thesis, Department of Linguistics, University of Geneva.
2017 “Connectives: Order, causality and beyond.” In Formal Models in the Study of Language, ed. by Joanna Blochowiak, Cristina Grisot, Stéphanie Dürrlemann-Tame and Christopher Laenzlinger. Cham: Springer.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Blochowiak, Joanna and Thomas Castelain
2018 “How logical is natural language conjunction? Am experimental investigation of the French conjunction et .” In Language, Evolution, and Mind: Essays in Honor of Anne Reboul, ed. by Pierre Saint-Germier, 97–125. London: College Publications.Google Scholar
Borg, Emma
2012 “Semantics without pragmatics?” In The Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. by. Keith Allan and Kasia M. Jaszczolt, 513–528. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2004Minimal Semantics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Brown, Penelope and Stephen C. Levinson
1987Politeness: Some Universals in Language Use. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Carston, Robyn
2002Thoughts and Utterances: The Pragmatics of Explicit Communication. Oxford: Blackwell.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Chierchia, Gennaro
2013Logic in Grammar: Polarity, Free Choice, and Intervention. Oxford: Oxford University Press.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Cohen, L. Jonathan
1971 “Some remarks on Grice’s view about the logical particles of natural language.” In Pragmatics of Natural Language, ed. by Yoshua Bar-Hillel, 50–68. Dordrecht: Reidel.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Cole, Peter
1981 “Preface”. In Radical Pragmatics, ed. by Peter Cole, xi–xiv. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Escandell-Vidal, Victoria, Manuel Leonetti and Aoife Ahern
(eds) 2011Procedural Meaning: Problems and Perspectives. Bingley: Emerald Brill.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Fodor, Jerry A.
1975The Language of Thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
2008LOT 2: The Language of Thought Revisited. Oxford: Oxford University Press.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Gazdar, Gerald
1979Pragmatics: Implicature, Presupposition, and Logical Form. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Grice, H. Paul
1975 “Logic and conversation.” In Syntax and Semantics 3: Speech Acts, ed. by Peter Cole and Jerry L. Morgan, 41–58. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
1989Studies in the Way of Words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Grisot, Cristina
2015Temporal Reference: Empirical and Theoretical Perspectives. Converging Evidence from English and Romance. PhD thesis, Department of Linguistics, University of Geneva.
Grisot, Cristina and Jacques Moeschler
2014 “How do empirical methods interact with theoretical pragmatics? The conceptual and procedural contents of the English Simple Past and its translation into French.” In Yearbook of Corpus Linguistics and Pragmatics 2014: New Empirical and Theoretical Paradigms, ed. by Jesus Romero-Trillo, 7–33. Cham: Springer.Google Scholar
Hauser, Marc
1996The Evolution of Communication. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Horn, Laurence R.
1984 “Towards a new taxonomy for pragmatic inference: Q-based and R-based implicature.” In Meaning, Form and Use in Context. GURT 84, ed. by Deborah Schiffrin, 11–42. Washington: Georgetown University Press.Google Scholar
1989A Natural History of Negation. Chicago. The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
2004 “Implicature.” In The Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. by Laurence Horn and Gregory Ward, 3–28. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Huang, Yan
2014Pragmatics, 2nd edition. Oxford. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Karttunen, Lauri and Stanley Peters
1979 “Conventional implicatures”. In Syntax and Semantics 11: Presupposition, ed. by Choon-kyu Oh and David A. Dinneen, 1–56. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Keenan, Edward
1978 “On surface form and logical form.” In Linguistics in the Seventies: Directions and Prospects, ed. by Braj B. Kachru, 163–203. Special issue of Studies in Linguistic Sciences 8(2).Google Scholar
Korta, Kepa and John Perry
2011Critical Pragmatics An Inquiry into Reference and Communication. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Levinson, Stephen C.
2000Presumptive Meanings: The Theory of Generalized Conversational Implicature. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Montague, Richard
1970 “Pragmatics and intensional logic”. Synthese 22: 68–94.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Moeschler, Jacques
2007 “The role of explicature in communication and in intercultural communication”. In Explorations in Pragmatics: Linguistic, Cognitive and Intercultural Aspects, ed. by Istvan Kecskes and Laurence R. Horn, 73–94. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.Google Scholar
2011 “Causal, inferential and temporal connectives: Why parce que is the only causal connective in French.” In Marqueurs discursifs et subjectivité, ed. by Sylvie Hancil, 97–114. Rouen: Presses Universitaires de Rouen et du Havre.Google Scholar
2013a “Is a speaker-based pragmatics possible? Or how can a hearer infer a speaker’s commitment?Journal of Pragmatics 43: 84–97.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2013b “How ‘logical’ are logical words? Negation and its descriptive vs. metalinguistic uses.” In Nonveridicality and Evaluation. Theoretical, Computational and Corpus Approaches, ed. by Maite Taboada and Radoslava Trnavac, 76–110. Leiden: Brill.Google Scholar
2016a “Where is procedural meaning? Evidence from discourse connectives and tenses.” Lingua 175-176: 122–138.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2016b “Avec ou sans? Une approche pragmatique des discours causaux explicités et implicités” [With or without? A pragmatic approach of explicit and implicit causal discourses]. In The Grammar of Causation, ed. by Stéphane Viellard Irina Thomièresand , 36–51. Paris: CeliSo.Google Scholar
2017a “Formal and natural languages: What does logic tell us about natural language?” In The Routledge Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. by Anne Barron A., Gerard Steen and Gu Yueguo, 241–256. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
2017b “Back to negative particulars. A truth-conditional account.” In Pragmatics and its Interfaces, ed. by Stavros Assimakopoulos, 9–31. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.Google Scholar
2018 “Representation and metarepresentation in negation.” In Relevance Theory: Pragmatics and Interpretation, ed. by Robyn Carston, Kate Scott and Billy Clark. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Noveck, Ira and Dan Sperber
2007 “The why and how of experimental pragmatics: The case of ‘scalar implicatures’.” In Pragmatics, ed. by Noel Burton-Roberts, 184–212. Basingstoke: Palgrave.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Potts, Christopher
2005The Logic of Conventional Implicatures. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Reboul, Anne
2004 “Conversational Implicatures: Nonce or Generalized?” In Experimental Pragmatics, ed. by Ira Noveck and Dan Sperber, 322–333. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2017Cognition and Communication in the Evolution of Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Reboul, Anne and Jacques Moeschler
1998La pragmatique aujourd’hui : Une nouvelle science de la communication [Pragmatics Today. A New Science of Communication]. Paris: Seuil.Google Scholar
Recanati, François
2002 “Unarticulated constituents.” Linguistics and Philosophy 25: 299–345.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2004Literal Meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University press.Google Scholar
2010Truth-Conditional Pragmatics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Reichenbach, Hans
1947Elements of Symbolic Logic. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Sasamoto, Ryoko and Deirdre Wilson
(eds) 2016Little Words: Communication and Procedural Meaning. Special issue of Lingua 175–176.Google Scholar
Searle, John R.
1983Intentionality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Sperber, Dan and Deirdre Wilson
1986Relevance. Communication and Cognition. Oxford. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Sadock, Jerrold M.
1978 “On testing for conversational implicature.” In Syntax and Semantics 9: Pragmatics, ed. by Peter Cole, 281–297. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, Deirdre
2003 “Relevance and lexical pragmatics.” Italian Journal of Linguistics 15(2): 273–291.Google Scholar
Wilson, Deirdre and Robyn Carston
2007 “A unitary approach to lexical pragmatics: Relevance, inference and ad hoc concepts.” In Pragmatics, ed. by Noel Burton-Roberts, 230–259. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Wilson, Deirdre and Dan Sperber
1993 “Linguistic form and relevance”. Lingua 90(1–2): 1–25.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2004 “Relevance theory.” In The Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. by Laurence R. Horn and Gregory Ward, 607–632. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
2012Meaning and Relevance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Zufferey, Sandrine, Jacques Moeschler and Anne Reboul
Forthcoming. Implicatures. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.DOI logo