Relevance theory

Diane Blakemore
Table of contents

Sperber & Wilson’s relevance theory, presented most fully in Sperber & Wilson (1986), is an approach to communication and utterance understanding based on a general view of cognition. In contrast with formal approaches to pragmatics (e.g. Gazdar 1979) and socio-cultural approaches (e.g. Leech 1983), relevance theory views pragmatic interpretation as a psychological matter involving inferential computations performed over mental representations, governed by a single cognitive principle. The assumption underlying this approach is that the mind is modular, and, in particular, that there is a distinction between linguistic computations and representations on the one hand, and non-linguistic computations and representations on the other. It is this psychological distinction which, according to relevance theory, underlies the distinction between semantics and pragmatics.

Full-text access is restricted to subscribers. Log in to obtain additional credentials. For subscription information see Subscription & Price.

References

Austin, J.L.
1962How to do things with words. Clarendon Press. Google Scholar
Blakemore, D.
1987Semantic constraints on relevance. Blackwell. Google Scholar
1988‘So’ as a constraint on relevance. In R. Kempson (ed.): 183–195. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
1991Performatives and parentheticals. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 91: 197–214. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
1992Understanding utterances. Blackwell.  BoPGoogle Scholar
1993The relevance of reformulations. Language and Literature 2(2): 101–120. Google Scholar
Blass, R.
1990Relevance relations in Sissala. Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Carston, R.
1988aLanguage and cognition. In F. Newmeyer (ed.) Linguistics, vol. 3: 38–68. Cambridge University Press.  BoPGoogle Scholar
1988bImplicature, explicature and truth-theoretic semantics. In R. Kempson (ed.): 155–181.  BoPGoogle Scholar
1993Conjunction, explanation and relevance. Lingua 90(2): 27–48. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Clark, B.
1991Relevance theory and the semantics of non-declarative sentences. PhD. Diss., University College London. Google Scholar
Fodor, J.
1983The modularity of mind. MIT Press.  BoPGoogle Scholar
Gazdar, G.
1979Pragmatics. Academic Press.  BoPGoogle Scholar
Grice, H.P.
1975Logic and conversation. In P. Cole & J. Morgan (eds.) Syntax and Semantics, vol. 3: 41–58. Academic Presscademic Press.  BoPGoogle Scholar
1978Further notes on logic and conversation. In P. Cole (ed.) Syntax and Semantics vol. 9: 113–28. Academic Presscademic Press. Google Scholar
1989Studies in the way of words. Harvard University Press. Google Scholar
Kempson, R.
1988On the grammar-cognition interface. In R. Kempson (ed.): 199–224. Cambridge University Press.  BoPGoogle Scholar
(ed.) 1988Mental representations. Cambridge University Press.  BoPGoogle Scholar
Leech, G.
1983Principles of pragmatics. Longman.  BoPGoogle Scholar
Levinson, S.
1983Pragmatics. Cambridge University Press.  BoPGoogle Scholar
Récanati, F.
1987Meaning and force. Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Searle, J.R.
1979The classification of speech acts. In J.R. Searle, Expression and meaning: 1–29. Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Sperber, D. & D. Wilson
1981Irony and the use-mention distinction. In P. Cole (ed.) Radical pragmatics: 295–318. Academic Presscademic Press. DOI logo  BoPGoogle Scholar
1986Relevance. Blackwell.  BoPGoogle Scholar
1985/6Loose talk. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 86: 153–171.  BoP DOI logoGoogle Scholar
1987Precis of ‘Relevance’. Behavioural and Brain Sciences 10: 697–754. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
1990Rhetoric and relevance. In D. Wellbery & J. Bender (eds.) The ends of rhetoric: 140–145. Stanford University Presstanford University Press. Google Scholar
Wilson, D. & D. Sperber
1981On Grice’s theory of conversation. In P. Werth (ed.) Conversation and discourse: 155–178. Croom Helm.  BoPGoogle Scholar
1986aPragmatics and modularity. In A. Farley, P. Farley & K. Mccullough (eds.) Chicago Linguistics Society 22, Part 2: 67–84.  BoPGoogle Scholar
1986bInference and implicature. In C. Travis (ed.) Meaning and interpretation: 45–76. Blackwell.  BoPGoogle Scholar
1988Mood and the analysis of non-declarative sentences. In J. Dancy et al. (eds.) Human agency: 77–101. Stanford University Presstanford University Press.  BoPGoogle Scholar
1992aOn verbal irony. Lingua 87: 53–76. DOI logo  BoPGoogle Scholar
1992bReference and relevance. University College Working Papers in Linguistics 4: 167–192. Google Scholar
1993Linguistic form and relevance. Lingua 90(2): 1–26. DOI logoGoogle Scholar