Intentionality

Jan Nuyts
Table of contents

This contribution is meant to offer a brief introduction to (some of) the intricacies of the notion of human intentions and intentionality, with special reference to their role in language behavior. Intention/intentionality is meant here (in a narrow sense – see below) as the theoretical concept which is generally invoked to account for the purposefulness or goal-directedness of human behavior (or ‘action’), linguistic and otherwise. Intuitively, this is a straightforward concept. It is an essential part of our ‘folk psychology’: we often wonder whether things people do are intentional (i.e., done on purpose) or not, and the notion is thereby taken to refer to an element ‘inside’ a person which motivates him/her to act in certain ways. (Thus, the notion is crucial in determining ‘guilt’ in many legal systems.) Not surprisingly, then, the term is quite common in ‘ordinary’ language use: utterances like sorry, I didn’t do that intentionally or beware of that guy, his intentions are bad or I intend to finish that paper by tomorrow sound very familiar. Scientifically, however, the notion turns out to be extremely volatile and difficult to grasp. Especially in philosophy, it has received some attention, yet without this leading – not even remotely – to a consensus even on the bare essentials of what a theory of intentionality ought to look like. And although most (empirical-)scientific theories of human behavior axiomatically accept the notion (explicitly or implicitly) as a critical ‘causal force’, very few dare to venture into its nature and phenomenology. Hence, basic questions such as ‘what is intentionality’ (beyond the almost tautological statement that it involves having a purpose or an aim with something), ‘how does it work’, ‘how does it relate to (types of) behavior’, ‘how should it be situated in a wider concept of human cognitive and social functioning’, etc. remain largely unresolved. Thus, the notion belongs in the ‘hall of scientific mysteries’, next to notions such as ‘self’, ‘consciousness’, ‘attention’, or ‘will’ (many of which are no doubt directly related to the concept of intentionality – see Section 1).

Full-text access is restricted to subscribers. Log in to obtain additional credentials. For subscription information see Subscription & Price.

References

Anscombe, G.E.M.
1957Intention. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Austin, J.L.
1962How to do things with words. Clarendon.Google Scholar
Brentano, F.
1874Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt. Ducker.Google Scholar
Du Bois, J.
1987Meaning without intention. Papers in Pragmatics 1(2): 80–122. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
1992Meaning without intention: Lessons from divination. In J.H. Hill & J.T. Irvine (eds.): 48–71.Google Scholar
Bratman, M.E.
1987Intention, plans, and practical reason. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
1990What is intention?. In P.R. Cohen et al. (eds.): 15–31.Google Scholar
Burkhardt, A.
(ed.) 1990Speech acts, meaning and intentions. De Gruyter. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Carbaugh, D.
(ed.) 1990Cultural communication and intercultural contact. Erlbaum.  BoPGoogle Scholar
Castañeda, H.-N.
1975Thinking and doing. Reidel. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Clark, H.H.
1992Arenas of language use. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
1996Using language. Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Clark, H.H. & D. Wilkes-Gibbs et al.
(eds.) 1990Referring as a collaborative process. In P.R. Cohen (eds.). 463–493. DOI logo  BoPGoogle Scholar
Cohen, P.R., J. Morgan & M.E. Pollack
(eds.) 1990Intentions in communication. MIT Press.  BoPGoogle Scholar
Copi, I.M.
1978Introduction to logic , 5th ed. Macmillan.Google Scholar
Dascal, M. & A. Idan
1989From individual to collective action. In F. Vandamme & R. Pinxten (eds.). The philosophy of Leo Apostel: 133–148. Communication and Cognition.Google Scholar
Davidson, D.
1980Essays on actions and events. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D.
1987The intentional stance. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Duranti, A.
1988Intentions, language, and social action in a Samoan context. Journal of Pragmatics 12: 13–33. DOI logo  BoPGoogle Scholar
1992Intentions self, and responsibility: An essay in Samoan ethnopragmatics. In J.H. Hill & J.T. Irvine (eds.): 24–47.Google Scholar
Fodor, J.A.
1975The language of thought. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
1987Psychosemantics. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Grice, H.P.
1957Meaning. Philosophical Review 66: 377–388. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
1969Utterer’s meaning and intentions. Philosophical Review 78: 147–177. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
1989Studies in the way of words. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Grosz, B.J. & C.L. Sidner
1990Plans for discourse. In P.R Cohen et al. (eds.): 417–444.Google Scholar
Harnish, R.M.
1990Speech acts and intentionality. In A. Burkhardt (ed.): 169–193.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Hill, J.H. & J.T. Irvine
(eds.) 1992Responsibility and evidence in oral discourse. Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hintikka, J.
1975The intentions of intentionality and other new models for modalities. Reidel. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Hobbs, J.
1990Artificial intelligence and collective intentionality. In CohenP.R et al. (eds.): 445–459.Google Scholar
Husserl, E.
1913Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. Niemeyer.Google Scholar
Hymes, D.
1990Epilogue to The things we do with words. In CarbaughD. (ed.): 419–429.Google Scholar
Jackendoff, R.
1983Semantics and Cognition. MIT-Press.Google Scholar
1987Consciousness and the Computational Mind. MIT Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Kempen, G.
1977Man’s sentence generator. In M De Mey et al. (eds.) CC77: 157–164. Communication and Cognition.  BoPGoogle Scholar
Levelt, W.J.M.
1989Speaking. MIT Press.Google Scholar
Liedtke, F.W.
1990Representational semantics and illocutionary acts. In A. Burkhardt (ed.): 194–209.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Mccawley, J.D.
1981Everything that linguists have always wanted to know about logic but were ashamed to ask. University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Meinong, A.
1904Untersuchungen zur Gegenstandstheorie und Psychologie. Barth.Google Scholar
Nuyts, J.
1992Aspects of a cognitive-pragmatic theory of language. John Benjamins.  BoPGoogle Scholar
1993aIntentions and the functions of language in communication. Protosoziologie 4:15–31.Google Scholar
1993bRepresentation and communication: Searle’s distinction revisited. Journal of Pragmatics 20: 591–597. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
1993cOn determining the functions of language. Semiotica 94: 201–232. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
1994The intentional and the sociocultural in language use. Pragmatics & Cognition 2: 237–268. DOI logo  BoPGoogle Scholar
Rossaldo, M.Z.
1982The things we do with words. Language in Society 11: 203–237. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Schneider, W. & R.M. Shiffrin
1977Controlled and automatic human information processing, I: Detection, search, and attention. Psychological Review 84: 1–66. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Searle, J.R.
1969Speech acts. Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
1983Intentionality. Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
1986Meaning, communication, and representation. In R. Grandy & R. Warner (eds.) Philosophical grounds of rationality: 209–226. Clarendon.Google Scholar
1989Individual intentionality and social phenomena in the theory of speech acts. In G. Deledalle (ed.) Semiotics and pragmatics: 3–17. John Benjamins. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
1990aCollective intentions and actions. In P.R Cohen et al. (eds.): 401–415.Google Scholar
1990bEpilogue to the taxonomy of illocutionary acts. In D. Carbaugh (ed.): 409–417.Google Scholar
Shiffrin, R.M. & W. Schneider
1977Controlled and automatic human information processing, II: Perceptual learning, automatic attending, and a general theory. Psychological Review 84: 127–190. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Stalnaker, R.
1984Inquiry. MIT Press.  MetBibGoogle Scholar
Tuomela, R. & K. Miller
1988We-intentions. Philosophical Studies 53: 367–389. DOI logoGoogle Scholar