Polar answers and epistemic stance in Greek conversation
Abstract
This conversation analytic study examines the linguistic resources for indexing epistemic stance in second position in question sequences in Greek conversation. It targets three formats for providing affirming/confirming answers to polar questions: unmarked and marked positive response tokens, and repetitions. It is shown that the three formats display different functional distributions. Unmarked response tokens do ‘simple’ answering, marked response tokens provide overt confirmations, and repetitional answers assert the respondent’s epistemic authority besides confirming the question’s proposition. Unmarked and marked response tokens accept the questioner’s epistemic stance, whereas repetitional answers may accept or resist the epistemic terms of the question, depending on the action being implemented by the question. This study sheds light on the organization of questioning and answering in Greek conversation and the role of epistemics in the design of polar answers.
Keywords:
Publication history
1.Introduction
This paper examines epistemic stance taking in polar answers in Greek conversation. More specifically, the analysis targets three formats for providing affirming/confirming polar answers, namely unmarked response tokens, marked response tokens, and repetitions, and demonstrates that these formats convey the respondent’s different positioning towards the questioner’s epistemic stance and the proposition in question.
Epistemic stance refers to speaker’s positioning towards an object related to knowledge. According to Ochs (1996Ochs, Elinor 1996 “Linguistic Resources for Socializing Humanity.” In Rethinking Linguistic Relativity, ed. by John Gumperz and Stephen Levinson, 407–437. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press., 422), epistemic stance includes “qualities of knowledge, such as degrees of certainty of knowledge as to the truth of a proposition and sources of knowledge”. Stance taking is an interactional achievement (Du Bois 2007Du Bois, John W. 2007 “The Stance Triangle.” In Stancetaking in Discourse: Subjectivity, Evaluation, Interaction, ed. by Robert Englebretson, 139–182. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. ; Heritage 2012 2012 “Epistemics in Action: Action Formation and Territories of Knowledge.” Research on Language and Social Interaction 45(1): 1–29. ) that emerges across successive utterances, it is context dependent and inference based. Prior research (see e.g. Aikhenvald 2004Aikhenvald, Alexandra Y. 2004 Evidentiality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.; Biber and Finegan 1989Biber, Douglas, and Edward Finegan 1989 “Styles of Stance in English: Lexical and Grammatical Marking of Evidentiality and Affect.” Text 9(1): 93–124.; Chafe and Nichols 1986Chafe, Wallace L., and Johanna Nichols (eds) 1986 Evidentiality: The Linguistic Coding of Epistemology. Norwood, New Jersey: Ablex Publishing Corporation.; Clift 2006Clift, Rebecca 2006 “Indexing Stance: Reported Speech as an Interactional Evidential.” Journal of Sociolinguistics 10(5): 569–595. ; Fox 2001Fox, Barbara A. 2001 “Evidentiality: Authority, Responsibility, and Entitlement in English conversation.” Journal of Linguistic Anthropology 11(2): 167–192. ; Heritage 2012 2012 “Epistemics in Action: Action Formation and Territories of Knowledge.” Research on Language and Social Interaction 45(1): 1–29. ; Heritage and Sorjonen 2018Heritage, John, and Marja-Leena Sorjonen (eds) 2018 Between Turn and Sequence: Turn-Initial Particles across Languages. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. ; Kärkkäinen 2003Kärkkäinen, Elise 2003 Epistemic Stance in English Conversation: A Description of its Interactional Functions, with a Focus on I think. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. ; Kärkkäinen 2006 2006 “Stance Taking in Conversation: From Subjectivity to Intersubjectivity.” Text and Talk 26(6): 699–731. ; Wu 2004Wu, Ruey-Jiuan R. 2004 Stance in Talk: A Conversation Analysis of Mandarin Final Particles. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. ) has shown that epistemic stance taking is accomplished through various linguistic resources, such as grammaticalized evidentiality, verbs, adverbs, parentheticals, particles, prosody, and interrogative syntax. This study examines the linguistic resources that speakers use to index epistemic stance in second position in question sequences, namely response tokens and repeats. Unlike items such as seem, evidently or I think which are explicitly marked for epistemic stance, response tokens and repeats in polar answers convey an epistemic meaning as a result of their sequential position and the action performed. In this introduction, I offer some theoretical preliminaries on epistemic stance in polar question-answer sequences and I contextualize my research question within the broader framework of conversation analytic studies of epistemics and polar answers.
1.1Questions and answers
Polar questions (also known as yes/no questions) “present whole propositions as hypotheses” to be affirmed/denied or confirmed/disconfirmed (Couper-Kuhlen and Selting 2018Couper-Kuhlen, Elizabeth, and Margret Selting 2018 Interactional Linguistics: Studying Language in Social Interaction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press., 224), and they are defined both formally and functionally (De Ruiter 2012De Ruiter, Jan P. 2012 “Introduction.” In Questions: Formal, Functional and Interactional Perspectives, ed. by Jan P. De Ruiter, 1–8. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. , 2). That is, polar questions can be coded grammatically (e.g. via V-S inversion in English), morphosyntactically (e.g. via sentence-final particles in Lao, Enfield 2010Enfield, N. J. 2010 “Questions and Responses in Lao.” Journal of Pragmatics 42(10): 2649–2665. ) or prosodically (e.g. via final rising intonation in Greek, as discussed in Section 1.2). Also, polar questions are interpreted on what they accomplish in interaction, that is, requests for information or confirmation, depending on whether the questioner positions her/himself as wholly unknowing or partially knowing.
Interlocutors’ epistemic status, that is, their relative access to some epistemic domain, is key in recognizing and interpreting questions. Heritage (2012 2012 “Epistemics in Action: Action Formation and Territories of Knowledge.” Research on Language and Social Interaction 45(1): 1–29. , 4) considers “relative epistemic access to a domain or territory of information as stratified between interactants such that they occupy different positions on an epistemic gradient (more knowledgeable [K+] or less knowledgeable [K−]), which itself may vary in slope from shallow to deep”. The moment-by-moment expression of epistemic status as managed through the design of turns at talk is described by Heritage (2012 2012 “Epistemics in Action: Action Formation and Territories of Knowledge.” Research on Language and Social Interaction 45(1): 1–29. , 6) as epistemic stance. Polar questions indicate epistemic asymmetry between interlocutors, as questioners (K−) usually request information that falls into respondents’ (K+) epistemic domain (Heritage 2012 2012 “Epistemics in Action: Action Formation and Territories of Knowledge.” Research on Language and Social Interaction 45(1): 1–29. ; Heritage and Raymond 2012 2012 “Navigating Epistemic Landscapes: Acquiescence, Agency and Resistance in Responses to Polar Questions.” In Questions: Formal, Functional and Interactional Perspectives, ed. by Jan P. De Ruiter, 179–192. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ). The ways in which interlocutors express their epistemic status through the design of questions and answers are discussed below.
The depth of the K−/K+ epistemic gradient between questioner and respondent can be adjusted by means of the question design. For example, Heritage (2012 2012 “Epistemics in Action: Action Formation and Territories of Knowledge.” Research on Language and Social Interaction 45(1): 1–29. , 6) observes that the English polar interrogative (i) Are you married? positions the questioner as less knowledgeable than the respondent, whereas the tag question (ii) You’re married, aren’t you? and the declarative question (iii) You’re married. positions the questioner as somewhat more knowing, seeking confirmation for information that is already in play. Utterance (i) indexes “a deeply sloping epistemic gradient between an unknowing (K−) questioner and a knowing (K+) recipient”, whereas utterances (ii) and (iii) index “increasingly shallow K− to K+ epistemic gradients” (Heritage 2012 2012 “Epistemics in Action: Action Formation and Territories of Knowledge.” Research on Language and Social Interaction 45(1): 1–29. , 6). This is depicted in Figure 1.
In all three utterances, the respondent is positioned as having primary epistemic rights over the information at issue. However, in (i) the questioner is positioned as having no epistemic rights, whereas in (ii) and (iii) the questioner claims more epistemic rights over the information at issue (for a thorough discussion see Heritage and Raymond 2005Heritage, John, and Geoffrey Raymond 2005 “The Terms of Agreement: Indexing Epistemic Authority and Subordination in Talk-in-Interaction.” Social Psychology Quarterly 68(1): 15–38. ; Raymond and Heritage 2006Raymond, Geoffrey, and John Heritage 2006 “The Epistemics of Social Relations: Owning Grandchildren.” Language in Society 35(5): 677–705. ).
Also, the depth of the K−/K+ epistemic gradient between questioner and respondent can be adjusted by means of the derived action being implemented by the polar question. According to Schegloff (2007 2007 Sequence Organization in Interaction: A Primer in Conversation Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. , 169), questions are turn types with a “double duty”, that is, they enact their own action (questioning) and serve thereby “as the vehicle or instrument for another action.” For example, a polar question implements a request for information, i.e. a vehicular action (Sidnell 2017Sidnell, Jack 2017 “Action in Interaction is Conduct under a Description.” Language in Society 46(3): 313–337. , 325), which in turn may carry out a disagreement or confirming an allusion, i.e. a derived action (Sidnell 2017Sidnell, Jack 2017 “Action in Interaction is Conduct under a Description.” Language in Society 46(3): 313–337. , 326). Disagreeing or confirming an allusion are actions that challenge the respondent’s epistemic authority, that is, their “relative rights to know about some state of affairs” (Stivers et al. 2011Stivers, Tanya, Lorenza Mondada, and Jakob Steensig 2011 “Knowledge, Morality and Affiliation in Social Interaction.” In The Morality of Knowledge in Conversation. ed. by Tanya Stivers, Lorenza Mondada and Jakob Steensig, 3–24. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. , 13), and imply the questioner’s primary epistemic rights over the matter in question (Heritage and Raymond 2012 2012 “Navigating Epistemic Landscapes: Acquiescence, Agency and Resistance in Responses to Polar Questions.” In Questions: Formal, Functional and Interactional Perspectives, ed. by Jan P. De Ruiter, 179–192. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ; Schegloff 1996Schegloff, Emanuel A. 1996 “Confirming Allusions: Toward an Empirical Account of Action.” American Journal of Sociology 102(1): 161–216. ). As Heritage and Raymond (2012 2012 “Navigating Epistemic Landscapes: Acquiescence, Agency and Resistance in Responses to Polar Questions.” In Questions: Formal, Functional and Interactional Perspectives, ed. by Jan P. De Ruiter, 179–192. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. , 181) observe, “polar questions, while acknowledging the epistemic rights of respondents, also tend to restrict the exercise of those rights”. The epistemic stance conveyed by the questioner has implications for the design of the respondent’s turn.
Questions anticipate and receive responses from addressed recipients (Schegloff 2007 2007 Sequence Organization in Interaction: A Primer in Conversation Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. , 78; see studies in Enfield et al. 2010Enfield, N. J., Tanya Stivers, and Stephen C. Levinson (eds.) 2010 Question-Response Sequences in Conversation across Ten Languages: Special issue of Journal of Pragmatics 42(10). ). In their cross-linguistic study, Enfield et al. (2019)Enfield, N. J., Tanya Stivers, Penelope Brown, Christina Englert, Katariina Harjunpää, Makoto Hayashi, Trine Heinemann, Gertie Hoymann, Tiina Keisanen, Mirka Rauniomaa, Chase Raymond, Federico Rossano, Kyung-Eun Yoon, Inge Zwitserlood, Stephen Levinson 2019 “Polar Answers.” Journal of Linguistics 55(2): 277–304. identified two main formats for delivering confirming polar answers: interjection-type answers, such as yes, yeah or mm-hm, which are generally preferred, and repetition-type answers that fully or partially repeat elements of the question. Enfield et al. (2019)Enfield, N. J., Tanya Stivers, Penelope Brown, Christina Englert, Katariina Harjunpää, Makoto Hayashi, Trine Heinemann, Gertie Hoymann, Tiina Keisanen, Mirka Rauniomaa, Chase Raymond, Federico Rossano, Kyung-Eun Yoon, Inge Zwitserlood, Stephen Levinson 2019 “Polar Answers.” Journal of Linguistics 55(2): 277–304. showed that the two formats have different functional distributions. Interjection-type answers “represent a solution to the problem of how to answer a polar question and do nothing more than that” (p. 281), whereas repetition-type answers are pragmatically marked “relative to this simple function” (p. 282).
In American English conversation, speakers use interjection-type answers to “accept the terms of the question unconditionally, exerting no agency with respect to those terms, and thus acquiescing in them” (Heritage and Raymond 2012 2012 “Navigating Epistemic Landscapes: Acquiescence, Agency and Resistance in Responses to Polar Questions.” In Questions: Formal, Functional and Interactional Perspectives, ed. by Jan P. De Ruiter, 179–192. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. , 183; see also Raymond 2003Raymond, Geoffrey 2003 “Grammar and Social Organization: Yes/No Interrogatives and the Structure of Responding.” American Sociological Review 68(6): 939–967. ). Marked or upgraded interjections, such as of course, certainly or absolutely, serve “to underscore the question recipient’s acceptance of the terms of the question” and also display the respondent’s problem “not with the question’s design but with it having been posed to this recipient at all – a problem with the legitimacy of the action of requesting information, requesting confirmation, and so on” (Stivers 2019 2019 “How we Manage Social Relationships through Answers to Questions: The Case of Interjections”. Discourse Processes 56(3): 191–209. , 8; see also Stivers 2011 2011 “Morality and Question Design: Of course as Contesting a Presupposition of Askability.” In The Morality of Knowledge in Conversation, ed. by Tanya Stivers, Lorenza Mondada and Jakob Steensig, 82–106. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ). To resist or challenge the socioepistemic constraints of a polar question English speakers use repetition-type answers (see e.g. Heritage and Raymond 2012 2012 “Navigating Epistemic Landscapes: Acquiescence, Agency and Resistance in Responses to Polar Questions.” In Questions: Formal, Functional and Interactional Perspectives, ed. by Jan P. De Ruiter, 179–192. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ; Raymond 2003Raymond, Geoffrey 2003 “Grammar and Social Organization: Yes/No Interrogatives and the Structure of Responding.” American Sociological Review 68(6): 939–967. ; Schegloff 1996Schegloff, Emanuel A. 1996 “Confirming Allusions: Toward an Empirical Account of Action.” American Journal of Sociology 102(1): 161–216. ; Stivers 2005Stivers, Tanya 2005 “Modified Repeats: One Method for Asserting Primary Rights from Second Position.” Research on Language and Social Interaction 38(2): 131–158. ) or transformative answers (Stivers and Hayashi 2010Stivers, Tanya, and Makoto Hayashi 2010 “Transformative Answers: One Way to Resist a Question’s Constraints.” Language in Society 39(1): 1–25. ). On the one hand, respondents use repetition to assert their “epistemic and social entitlement in regard to the matter being addressed” and claim “more epistemic rights over the information required than the original polar question conceded” (Heritage and Raymond 2012 2012 “Navigating Epistemic Landscapes: Acquiescence, Agency and Resistance in Responses to Polar Questions.” In Questions: Formal, Functional and Interactional Perspectives, ed. by Jan P. De Ruiter, 179–192. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. , 188). On the other hand, speakers can design their answers in ways that transform the question’s terms or agenda to resist the presuppositions of the questioner, the terms in which the question is being asked or what the questioner is trying to accomplish with the question (e.g. Question: He sold his place. Answer: Yeah I know) (Stivers and Hayashi 2010Stivers, Tanya, and Makoto Hayashi 2010 “Transformative Answers: One Way to Resist a Question’s Constraints.” Language in Society 39(1): 1–25. , 18).
Equivalent practices for designing polar answers are reported in other languages (see e.g. Lee 2015Lee, Seung-Hee 2015 “Two Forms of Affirmative Responses to Polar Questions.” Discourse Processes 52(1): 21–46. and Kim 2015Kim, Stephanie Hyeri 2015 “Resisting the Terms of Polar Questions Through Ani (‘No’)-Prefacing in Korean Conversation.” Discourse Processes 52(4): 311–334. on Korean, Keevallik 2010Keevallik, Leelo 2010 “Minimal Answers to Yes/No Questions in the Service of Sequence Organization.” Discourse Studies 12(3): 283–309. on Estonian, Sorjonen 2001aSorjonen, Marja-Leena 2001a Responding in Conversation: A Study of Response Particles in Finnish. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. , 2001b 2001b “Simple Answers to Polar Questions: The Case of Finnish.” In Studies in Interactional Linguistics, ed. by Margret Selting and Elizabeth Couper-Kuhlen, 405–431. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. on Finnish, Steensig and Heinemann 2013Steensig, Jakob, and Trine Heinemann 2013 “When Yes is not enough as an Answer to a Yes/No Question.” In Units of Talk – Units of Action, ed. by Beatrice Szczepek Reed and Geoffrey Raymond, 207–241. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. on Danish, Golato and Fagyal 2008Golato, Andrea, and Zsuzsanna Fagyal 2008 “Comparing Single and Double Sayings of the German Response Token Ja and the Role of Prosody: A Conversation Analytic Perspective.” Research on Language and Social Interaction 41(3): 241–270. on German, Seuren and Huiskes 2017Seuren, Lucas M., and Mike Huiskes 2017 “Confirmation or Elaboration: What Do Yes/No Declaratives Want?” Research on Language and Social Interaction 50(2): 188–205. on Dutch, Bolden 2009Bolden, Galina B. 2009 “Beyond Answering: Repeat-Prefaced Responses in Conversation.” Communication Monographs 76(2): 121–143. , 2016 2016 “A Simple Da?: Affirming Responses to Polar Questions in Russian Conversation.” Journal of Pragmatics 100: 40–58. on Russian, and Weidner 2018Weidner, Matylda 2018 “Treating Something as Self-Evident: No-Prefaced Turns in Polish.” In Between Turn and Sequence: Turn-Initial Particles across Languages, ed. by John Heritage and Marja-Leena Sorjonen, 225–250. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. on Polish). For example, Bolden (2016) 2016 “A Simple Da?: Affirming Responses to Polar Questions in Russian Conversation.” Journal of Pragmatics 100: 40–58. reports that Russian speakers use the prosodically marked affirmative particle da to convey a congruent or incongruent evaluative stance towards an affectively charged question (e.g. to express affiliation or disaffiliation with the evaluative stance conveyed by a question that initiates repair and conveys the questioner’s surprise). By contrast, repetitional answers convey the respondent’s incongruent epistemic stance in confirming information as inferable from prior talk. In Finnish, repetitional answers may register the question as a request for information, confirm an allusion or offer an upgraded confirmation (Sorjonen 2001aSorjonen, Marja-Leena 2001a Responding in Conversation: A Study of Response Particles in Finnish. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. , 2001b 2001b “Simple Answers to Polar Questions: The Case of Finnish.” In Studies in Interactional Linguistics, ed. by Margret Selting and Elizabeth Couper-Kuhlen, 405–431. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. ). Also, in Tzeltal, a language spoken in Chiapas, Mexico, repetitional answers are the default form for a minimal affirming response and display shared epistemic access and agency between interlocutors (Brown 2010Brown, Penelope 2010 “Questions and Their Responses in Tzeltal.” Journal of Pragmatics 42(10): 2627–2648. ; Enfield et al. 2019Enfield, N. J., Tanya Stivers, Penelope Brown, Christina Englert, Katariina Harjunpää, Makoto Hayashi, Trine Heinemann, Gertie Hoymann, Tiina Keisanen, Mirka Rauniomaa, Chase Raymond, Federico Rossano, Kyung-Eun Yoon, Inge Zwitserlood, Stephen Levinson 2019 “Polar Answers.” Journal of Linguistics 55(2): 277–304. , 297–299). As Sorjonen (2018 2018 “Questions and Responses: On their Structural and Interactional Relationships.” In Ερωτήσεις-Απαντήσεις στην Προφορική Επικοινωνία [Questions-Answers in Talk-in-Interaction], ed. by Theodossia Pavlidou, 11–32. Thessaloniki: Institute of Modern Greek Studies., 27) argues, “information on languages such as Estonian, Finnish, Japanese and Tzeltal indicates that there may be a division of labor between particle and repetition responses according to the sequential and activity context of the question, its epistemic assumptions and formal design”.
To sum up, prior research on polar answers across different languages demonstrates universal preferences, as well as language- and context-specific variation. That is, in certain contexts interjections can be treated as non-aligning with the questioner’s agenda (as in the transformative answer Yeah I know in English conversation), and in certain languages (e.g. Tzeltal) repetitional answers can be treated as non-resisting the constraints of the question. How does Greek fit in the overall picture? To date, there is a gap in the literature regarding polar answers and their communicative import in Greek conversation. This study aims to fill this gap partly by offering an empirical analysis of polar answers from a conversation analytic perspective. In the next section, I provide an overview of the forms and functions of polar questions in Greek.
1.2Polar questions in Modern Greek
In Modern Greek a declarative (1a)–(b)11.Examples given in this section are invented. or subjunctive main clause (2a)–(b) can be turned into a positive or negative polar question through rising intonation towards the end of the utterance, as in (3a)–(b) and (4a)–(b):
-
aɣόrasebuy.3sg.pstkafé.coffee(m).acc.sg
‘She bought coffee.’
-
ðennegaɣόrasebuy.3sg.pstkafé.coffee(m).acc.sg
‘She did not buy coffee.’
-
nasbjvaɣorásibuy.3sg.pfvkafé.coffee(m).acc.sg
‘She should buy coffee.’
-
nasbjvminnegaɣorásibuy.3sg.pfvkafé.coffee(m).acc.sg
‘She should not buy coffee.’
-
aɣόrasebuy.3sg.pstkafé?coffee(m).acc.sg
‘Did she buy coffee?’
-
ðennegaɣόrasebuy.3sg.pstkafé?coffee(m).acc.sg
‘Didn’t she buy coffee?’
-
nasbjvaɣorásibuy.3sg.pfvkafé?coffee(m).acc.sg
‘Should she buy coffee?’
-
nasbjvminnegaɣorásibuy.3sg.pfvkafé?coffee(m).acc.sg
‘Shouldn’t she buy coffee?’
Tags are added after statements with normal declarative (falling) intonation and turn them into questions. Tags are delivered with final rising intonation and include the particle e, the phrases étsi ðen íne/ðen íne étsi, and clauses negating the main verb of the clause, as in (5a)–(b):
-
aɣόrasebuy.3sg.pstkafé.coffee(m).acc.sgétsisoðennegíne?cop.3sg.prs
‘She bought coffee. Didn’t she?’
-
aɣόrasebuy.3sg.pstkafé.coffee(m).acc.sgðennegaɣόrase?buy.3sg.pst
‘She bought coffee. Didn’t she?’
Polar questions in Greek are less routinely delivered with final falling intonation (Alvanoudi 2018Alvanoudi, Angeliki 2018 “Ερωτήσεις Ολικής Άγνοιας στην Ελληνική: Μορφές και Λειτουργίες [Polar Questions in Greek: Forms and Functions].” In Ερωτήσεις-Απαντήσεις στην Προφορική Επικοινωνία [Questions and Answers in Greek Talk-in-Interaction], ed. by Theodossia Pavlidou, 35–59. Thessaloniki: Institute of Modern Greek Studies.) and acquire their interrogative meaning because they are statements about a domain on which the respondent is an authority (Levinson 2012Levinson, Stephen C. 2012 “Interrogative Intimations: On a Possible Social Economics of Interrogatives.” In Questions: Formal, Functional and Interactional Perspectives, ed. by Jan P. De Ruiter, 11–32. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. , 27).
Prior research on polar questions in Greek conversation (Alvanoudi 2018Alvanoudi, Angeliki 2018 “Ερωτήσεις Ολικής Άγνοιας στην Ελληνική: Μορφές και Λειτουργίες [Polar Questions in Greek: Forms and Functions].” In Ερωτήσεις-Απαντήσεις στην Προφορική Επικοινωνία [Questions and Answers in Greek Talk-in-Interaction], ed. by Theodossia Pavlidou, 35–59. Thessaloniki: Institute of Modern Greek Studies.; Alvanoudi 2019b 2019b “ ‘May I Tell You Something?’: When Questions do not Anticipate Responses.” Text & Talk 39(4): 563–587. ; Bella and Mozer 2015Bella, Spyridoula, and Amalia Mozer 2015 “Αρνητικές Eρωτηματικές Προσκλήσεις: Συνέπειες για τη Δομή Προτίμησης [Negative-Interrogative Invitations: Consequences for Preference Organization].” In Ελληνική Γλώσσα και Προφορική Επικοινωνία [Greek Language and Oral Communication], ed. by Theodossia Pavlidou, 11–22. Thessaloniki: Institute of Modern Greek Studies.; Bella and Mozer 2018 2018 “What’s in a First? The Link between Impromptu Invitations and their Responses.” Journal of Pragmatics 125: 96–110. ; Pavlidou 1986Pavlidou, Theodossia 1986 “Nα Ρωτήσω Κάτι; Ερωτήσεις σε Υποτακτική [May I Αsk Something? Questions in the Subjunctive].” Studies in Greek Linguistics: 233–249.; Pavlidou 1991 1991 “Cooperation and the Choice of Linguistic Means: Some Evidence from the Use of the Subjunctive in Modern Greek.” Journal of Pragmatics 15(1): 11–42. ; and studies in Pavlidou 2018 (ed.) 2018 Ερωτήσεις-Απαντήσεις στην Προφορική Επικοινωνία [Questions-Answers in Talk-in-Interaction]. Thessaloniki: Institute of Modern Greek Studies.) demonstrates the multifunctionality of polar questions. For example, Greek speakers use polar questions to carry out impromptu invitations (Bella and Mozer 2015Bella, Spyridoula, and Amalia Mozer 2015 “Αρνητικές Eρωτηματικές Προσκλήσεις: Συνέπειες για τη Δομή Προτίμησης [Negative-Interrogative Invitations: Consequences for Preference Organization].” In Ελληνική Γλώσσα και Προφορική Επικοινωνία [Greek Language and Oral Communication], ed. by Theodossia Pavlidou, 11–22. Thessaloniki: Institute of Modern Greek Studies.; Bella and Mozer 2018 2018 “What’s in a First? The Link between Impromptu Invitations and their Responses.” Journal of Pragmatics 125: 96–110. ), requests for information or confirmation and other initiation of repair (Alvanoudi 2018Alvanoudi, Angeliki 2018 “Ερωτήσεις Ολικής Άγνοιας στην Ελληνική: Μορφές και Λειτουργίες [Polar Questions in Greek: Forms and Functions].” In Ερωτήσεις-Απαντήσεις στην Προφορική Επικοινωνία [Questions and Answers in Greek Talk-in-Interaction], ed. by Theodossia Pavlidou, 35–59. Thessaloniki: Institute of Modern Greek Studies.), and implement requests to say/do something (Pavlidou 1991 1991 “Cooperation and the Choice of Linguistic Means: Some Evidence from the Use of the Subjunctive in Modern Greek.” Journal of Pragmatics 15(1): 11–42. ) and secure multi-unit turns in interaction (Alvanoudi 2019b 2019b “ ‘May I Tell You Something?’: When Questions do not Anticipate Responses.” Text & Talk 39(4): 563–587. ). A preliminary attempt to map out the forms and functions of yes/no answers to polar questions in Greek conversation was undertaken by Alvanoudi (2019a) 2019a “Απαντήσεις σε Ερωτήσεις Ολικής Άγνοιας: Επιρρήματα, Μόρια και Τροποποιημένες Ετεροεπαναλήψεις [Responses to Polar Questions: Adverbs, Particles and Modified Repeats].” Studies in Greek Linguistics 39: 47–63., drawing on approximately 22 hours of audio-recorded conversations. The present study is based on the same and additional data, and focuses exclusively on affirming/confirming answers and epistemic stance. My research aim is to examine how respondents position themselves towards the questioner’s epistemic stance and the proposition in question through the design of their polar answers. Analytic methods for coding data are presented in Section 2. Findings are discussed in Section 3. Concluding remarks are in Section 4.
2.Data and method
Data analyzed in this study come from approximately 27 hours of 40 audio-recorded everyday conversations and 30 audio-recorded telephone calls among friends and relatives from the Corpus of Spoken Greek (Institute of Modern Greek Studies). A detailed description of the features of the corpus (e.g. data collection, size, etc.) is in Pavlidou (2016 2016 Καταγράφοντας την Ελληνική Γλώσσα [Making a Record of the Greek Language]. Thessaloniki: Institute of Modern Greek Studies., 41–59) (more information is available under http://ins.web.auth.gr/index.php?lang=en&Itemid=251). Conversations have been fully transcribed according to the standard conversation analytic conventions (cf. Jefferson 2004Jefferson, Gail 2004 “Glossary of Transcript Symbols with an Introduction.” In Conversation Analysis: Studies from the First Generation, ed. by Gene H. Lerner, 13–31. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. ; an abbreviated representation of transcription conventions following Couper-Kuhlen and Selting 2018Couper-Kuhlen, Elizabeth, and Margret Selting 2018 Interactional Linguistics: Studying Language in Social Interaction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.: 606–607 is in Appendix B).
Following Stivers and Enfield’s (2010)Stivers, Tanya and N. J. Enfield 2010 “A Coding Scheme for Question-Response Sequences in Conversation.” Journal of Pragmatics 42(10): 2620–2626. coding scheme for question-answer sequences in conversation, in order for a polar question and answer to be coded, the following criteria had to be met:
-
A question had to be either a formal question (i.e. via prosodic marking) or a functional question (i.e. requesting information, confirmation or seeking agreement).
-
Newsmarks and tags were coded as functional questions because they seek confirmation.
-
Questions in reported speech were not coded as questions.
-
Answers directly dealt with the question as put and they were verbal (given that data were audio-recorded). In line with Thompson et al. (2015Thompson, Sandra A., Barbara A. Fox, and Elizabeth Couper-Kuhlen 2015 Grammar in Everyday Talk: Building Responsive Actions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. , 3), polar answers are understood as responsive actions, that is, actions that “take up the action of an initiating action” and “are ‘typed’, that is, they are specific to a particular type of initiating action that they are understood to address (Schegloff 2007 2007 Sequence Organization in Interaction: A Primer in Conversation Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ).” For example, confirming or disconfirming is a typed-responsive action to an information-seeking initiating action and agreeing or disagreeing is a typed-responsive action to an assessing initiating action. I provide a quantitative description of the data in the following section.
2.1Quantitative data
Utterances with final rising intonation are the dominant polar question type, as shown in Table 1.
Polar question type | Percent/n |
---|---|
Final rising intonation | 94% (n = 784) |
Declarative | 1% (n = 12) |
Tag | 5% (n = 40) |
Total | 100% (n = 836) |
In line with Stivers and Enfield’s (2010)Stivers, Tanya and N. J. Enfield 2010 “A Coding Scheme for Question-Response Sequences in Conversation.” Journal of Pragmatics 42(10): 2620–2626. coding scheme, questions were coded as Requests for Information if “it seemed that there was no other primary action to be coded” (p. 2623) and getting new information was the only job the question was doing. Questions were coded as Requests for Confirmation if the questioner appeared to assume that the proposition raised by the question was probably true. Questions were coded as Other Initiations of Repair if they were dealing with a problem of hearing or understanding the prior turn. Questions that implement requests for action, suggestions, proposals and offers were coded in a single category. Other actions as well as questions that carried out more than one action were coded as Other. We can observe in Table 2 that requests for information and confirmation are the most common actions being implemented by polar questions.
Social action | Percent/n |
---|---|
Request for information | 30% (n = 250) |
Request for confirmation | 33% (n = 271) |
Other initiation of repair | 9% (n = 77) |
Proposal/offer/request | 11% (n = 96) |
Other (pre-announcement, disagreement, etc.) | 17% (n = 142) |
Total | 100% (n = 836) |
Following Thompson et al. (2015Thompson, Sandra A., Barbara A. Fox, and Elizabeth Couper-Kuhlen 2015 Grammar in Everyday Talk: Building Responsive Actions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. , 4), the first turn constructional unit (TCU) of a next turn was coded as a response. Table 3 shows that 85% of questions received a response.
Responses | Percent/n |
---|---|
Answer | 85% (n = 709) |
No response | 15% (n = 127) |
Total | 100% (n = 836) |
I collected 709 instances of answers to polar questions. The following answer types were identified: (a) interjection-type answers or response tokens (henceforth response tokens), that is, particles or adverbial items; (b) repetitions, that is, answers that involve a modified replication of a question through addition or omission; (c) combination answers that consist of response tokens followed by repeats, and (d) transformations, that is, answers that change the terms or the agenda of the question.
Polar answer type | Percent/n |
---|---|
Positive response token | 41% (n = 294) |
Positive response token-repetition combination | 1% (n = 5) |
Repetition | 15% (n = 104) |
Transformation | 22% (n = 156) |
Denial/disconfirmation/non-answers (I don’t know) | 21% (n = 150) |
Total | 100% (n = 709) |
As shown in Table 4, 57% of polar questions received an affirmation/confirmation, 22% of polar questions were responded to with a transformation, and 21% of polar questions received a disconfirming response or a non-answer. That is, in Greek there is a preference for affirming or confirming answers, as observed in other languages (Stivers et al. 2009Stivers, Tanya, N. J. Enfield, Penelope Brown, Christina Englert, Makoto Hayashi, Trine Heinemann, Gertie Hoymann, Federico Rossano, Jan P. De Ruiter, Kyung-Eun Yoon, and Stephen C. Levinson 2009 “Universals and Cultural Variation in Turn-Taking in Conversation.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America (PNAS) 106: 10587–10592. ). Moreover, in designing affirming/confirming polar answers Greek speakers rely most on response tokens. This finding aligns with the cross-linguistic preference for the use of interjections in polar answers reported by Enfield et al. (2019)Enfield, N. J., Tanya Stivers, Penelope Brown, Christina Englert, Katariina Harjunpää, Makoto Hayashi, Trine Heinemann, Gertie Hoymann, Tiina Keisanen, Mirka Rauniomaa, Chase Raymond, Federico Rossano, Kyung-Eun Yoon, Inge Zwitserlood, Stephen Levinson 2019 “Polar Answers.” Journal of Linguistics 55(2): 277–304. .
The present study focuses on affirming/confirming polar answers.22.Answers to polar questions that carry out directive and commissive acts, such as requests for action, offers or proposals were not included in the final analysis, given that these responsive actions are shaped by deontic stance rather than epistemic stance (cf. Thompson et al. 2015Thompson, Sandra A., Barbara A. Fox, and Elizabeth Couper-Kuhlen 2015 Grammar in Everyday Talk: Building Responsive Actions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. , 264–267). Following Stivers’ (2019) 2019 “How we Manage Social Relationships through Answers to Questions: The Case of Interjections”. Discourse Processes 56(3): 191–209. typology, positive response tokens were divided into: (a) unmarked response tokens, that include the prosodically unmarked particle ne (‘yes’), the monosyllabic particle m and the bisyllabic particle m(h)m, and (b) marked response tokens, that include upgraded and downgraded tokens. Upgraded tokens include particles, which are prosodically marked with higher pitch or increased loudness, such as ne (‘yes’), repeats, such as ne ne ne, and semantically emphatic adverbs, such as vévea (‘of course’) and enoíte (‘absolutely’). Downgraded tokens, such as málon (‘maybe, probably’), carry positive or negative valence and are less common in the data. We can observe in Tables 5 and 6 that 61% of positive response tokens are unmarked and 39% are marked. Most marked tokens are upgraded. Prosodically marked tokens are the most common ones, followed by semantically emphatic adverbs and repeats.
Positive response token type | Percent/n |
---|---|
Unmarked positive response token | 61% (n = 179) |
Marked positive response token | 39% (n = 115) |
Total | 100% (n = 294) |
Marked positive response token type | Percent/n | |
---|---|---|
Upgraded positive response token | ||
Prosodically marked response token | 46% (n = 53) | |
Repeat of response token | 21% (n = 24) | |
Semantically emphatic adverb | 31% (n = 36) | |
Downgraded positive response token | 2% (n = 2) | |
Total | 100% (n = 115) |
This study examines (a) positive response tokens (Sections 3.1 and 3.2), and (b) repetitional answers (Section 3.3). As for (a), the study focuses on unmarked positive response tokens (Section 3.1), and marked upgraded tokens (Section 3.2).
3.Analysis
3.1Unmarked positive response tokens
Speakers use unmarked positive response tokens to answer polar questions that request information, as shown in Extract (1). The exchange comes from a conversation among four friends, two females, Magdalini and Yota, and two males, Spiros and Grigoris. Magdalini has informed her interlocutors that uncle Nikos just called her.
1 Spi: =Αpό pú ín aftόs. from where cop.3sg.prs this.m.sg =Where is he from. 2 (0.9) 3 Yot: Αp tin Aθína:.= from def Athens From Athe:ns.= 4 Gri: -> =.h Αp tο sόi tu babá sas ítan?= from def family def.gen dad.gen your.pl cop.3sg.pst =.h Was he from your dad’s side?= 5 Yot: => =Νe. yes =Yes. 6 (1.1) 7 Gri: ʝaftό ðen don [°(gzérume).] for this neg him know.1pl That’s why we don’t [°(know) him.] 8 Spi: [ʝaftό- aftό] °θa leɣa. for this this fut say.1sg [That’s why- that’s] what °I was gonna say.
In line 1, Spyros uses a wh-question to elicit information about the uncle’s origin, and Yota provides the information in line 3. The wh-question positions the recipient as having [K+] status and expresses a steep epistemic gradient as it “advances no hypothesis for confirmation” and claims no knowledge over the information at issue (Heritage and Raymond 2012 2012 “Navigating Epistemic Landscapes: Acquiescence, Agency and Resistance in Responses to Polar Questions.” In Questions: Formal, Functional and Interactional Perspectives, ed. by Jan P. De Ruiter, 179–192. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. , 181). The recipient accepts the [K+] status by providing a response to the wh-question, and thus demonstrating that she has the information the questioner is seeking. The wh-question-answer sequence is followed by a polar question-answer sequence in lines 4–5, in which Grigoris uses a declarative clause with final rising intonation to request additional information about the uncle (‘Was he from your dad’s side?’, line 4), and Yota provides the affirming answer ne (‘yes’, line 5). The polar question positions the same recipient as the party “with epistemic rights with respect to the knowledge domain being addressed” (Heritage and Raymond 2012 2012 “Navigating Epistemic Landscapes: Acquiescence, Agency and Resistance in Responses to Polar Questions.” In Questions: Formal, Functional and Interactional Perspectives, ed. by Jan P. De Ruiter, 179–192. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. , 181). This domain is a Type 1 knowable (Pomerantz 1980Pomerantz, Anita 1980 “Telling my Side: “Limited Access” as a “Fishing” Device.” Sociological Inquiry 50: 186–198. ), which speakers have rights and obligations to know from firsthand experience. The polar question is the second question in a row of questions about the same person that treats the recipient as having knowledge about the person being talked about. The polar question positions the questioner as unknowing [K−] and implements a request for information. Yota provides the information via the simple positive response token ne that comes with no delay or further elaboration, and simply affirms the question’s proposition. Yota’s response fully acquiesces to the terms of the question, not taking issue with the questioner’s epistemic positioning.
Also, speakers use unmarked positive response tokens to answer polar questions that request simple confirmation, as in Extract (2).
1 Fot: >Prospaθúsa na káno káti állo vasiká.< = ((laughing..................................)) try.1sg.pst sbjv do.1sg something else actually >Actually I was trying to do something else.< = 2 Art: -> =Pçοs in aftόs. ʝaɲόtis íne? who cop.3sg.prs this.m.sg Yanniotis(m).sg cop.3sg.prs =Who is he. Is he from Ioannina? 3 Chr: => Μ:.= particle Mm:.=
Artemis’ turn in line 2 consists of two TCUs requesting information. In the first TCU, the speaker uses a wh-question (‘Who is he.’) that claims no knowledge at all and seeks a single, specific piece of information (Specifying Question, Thompson et al. 2015Thompson, Sandra A., Barbara A. Fox, and Elizabeth Couper-Kuhlen 2015 Grammar in Everyday Talk: Building Responsive Actions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. , 20). In the second TCU, the speaker uses a polar question (‘Is he from Ioannina?’) to offer a candidate answer (Pomerantz 1988 1988 “Offering a Candidate Answer: An Information Seeking Strategy.” Communication Monographs 55(4): 360–373. ) that demonstrates the speaker’s implied knowledge of the proposition in question. According to Pomerantz (1988 1988 “Offering a Candidate Answer: An Information Seeking Strategy.” Communication Monographs 55(4): 360–373. , 369), “in putting forth a candidate answer, a speaker recognizably offers the candidate answer as a likely possibility. The particular choice of candidate answer is treated as a display of the speaker’s knowledge of, and familiarity with, the situation.” Thus, the polar question in line 2 positions the respondent as [K+] and construes the questioner as “somewhat knowledgeable even while seeking information” (Pomerantz 1988 1988 “Offering a Candidate Answer: An Information Seeking Strategy.” Communication Monographs 55(4): 360–373. , 370). In line 3, Chrysi responds to Artemi’s polar question delivered in the second TCU (given the preference for contiguity in interaction, Schegloff 2007 2007 Sequence Organization in Interaction: A Primer in Conversation Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ) via the particle m with final falling intonation. The respondent confirms the candidate answer as a likely possibility and demonstrates that she treats herself as [K+].
A similar case is in Extract (3). Ourania has informed Chrysanthi that the name Ourania is common in Corfu and in the Peloponnese. The question of interest is in line 4.
1 Chr: =Έxo tin edíposi όmos όti pοlí Cerciréi have.1sg def impression but that many Corfu residents =But I think that many residents of Corfu 2 íne Pelop- (.) ts, ðilaðí éxune kataɣoʝí p- cop.3pl Pelop- click that is have.3pl origin are from the Pelop- (.) ts, that is they come 3 a:p tin Belopόniso.= from def Peloponnese fro:m the Peloponnese.= 4 Our: -> =Αlíθça e?= really particle =Really eh?= 5 Chr: => =°Νe. yes =°Yes.
In lines 1–3, Chrysanthi delivers an informing about the origin of many residents of Corfu, assuming that the recipient does not know and should know (Heritage 1984Heritage, Jοhn 1984 “A Change-of-State Token and Aspects of its Sequential Placement.” In Structures of Social Action: Studies in Conversation Analysis, ed. by J. Maxwell Aitkinson and John Heritage, 299–345. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.). In line 4, Ourania confirms the informativeness of the information provided by Chrysanthi with a newsmark (‘Really eh?’) that consists of a tag (i.e. the particle e). The newsmark highlights Ourania’s turn as newsworthy and seeks confirmation, encouraging more talk on the matter. The tag question positions the respondent as [K+] but “construes the questioner as partly in the know”, as “the information provided in the response is not treated as wholly new” for the questioner (Couper-Kuhlen and Selting 2018Couper-Kuhlen, Elizabeth, and Margret Selting 2018 Interactional Linguistics: Studying Language in Social Interaction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press., 238). In line 5, Chrysanthi confirms with the token ne (‘yes’). Her answer is latched onto Ourania’s question, without any inter-turn gap or turn initial delay that disrupts the contiguity between the first and second pair part of the adjacency pair. Chrysanthi provides a simple confirming response and assumes an epistemically [K+] position.
In the above segments, speakers use unmarked positive response tokens to answer polar questions that request information or simple confirmation, and accept the epistemic terms of the question. The communicative import of marked response tokens is analyzed in the next section.
3.2Marked positive response tokens
Greek speakers use marked positive response tokens to answer polar questions that implement ‘surprised’ repair initiation. One example is visible in Extract (4):
1 Our: = <Emís páli ti k- ti fáɣame?> we adv what what eat.1pl.pst = <We what- what did we eat?> 2 Vag: =A ne. [xθes to vráði.] ah yes yesterday def night =Oh yes. [Last night.] 3 Οur: [.h Εmís fáɣame] we eat.1pl.pst [.h We ate] 4 <maʝirítsa °xtes to vráði.> magirítsa yesterday def night <magirítsa soup °last night.> 5 ? .hh= 6 Our: =.h[h fáɣame maʝirí]tsa, eat.1pl.pst magirítsa =.h[h We ate magirí]tsa, 7 Μar: [Τi tο kalítero.] what def best [It’s the best.] 8 Οur: tin ésti[le i mána] mu: it send.3sg.pst def mother my my: [mother sent] it to me 9 Vag: [>Ε vévea.<] eh of course [>Eh of course.<] 10 Οur: me ðéma, .h= with package(n).acc.sg in a package, .h= 11 Μar: -> =((laugh)) me ðéma?= with package(n).acc.sg In a package?= 12 Οur: => =↑NE:[::. ]= ((laughing)) yes =↑YE:[::S.]= 13 Vag: [Íírθe,]= arrive.3sg.pst [It arrived,]= 14 Μar: =Κalá, pos re pe[ðʝá.] well how particle guys =Well, gu[ys] how is this possible?’ 15 Οur: [Αpό ] Cércira. from Corfu [From] Corfu.
Ourania informs her interlocutors that last night she ate a soup that her mum posted to her in a package (lines 3, 4, 6, 8, 10). In line 11, Maria initiates repair (‘In a package?’) using a partial questioning repeat of Ourania’s turn (Robinson 2013Robinson, Jeffrey 2013 “Epistemics, Action Formation and Other-Initiation of Repair: The Case of Partial Questioning Repeats.” In Conversational Repair and Human Understanding, ed. by Makoto Hayashi, Geoffrey Raymond and Jack Sidnell, 261–292. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.). The repair initiation is a polar question that seeks confirmation and positions the respondent as [K+]. Moreover, the question displays speaker’s surprise, as shown by the prosodic realization (higher pitch) of the turn and speaker’s laughter (Selting 1996Selting, Margret 1996 “Prosody as an Activity Type Distinctive Cue in Conversation: The Case of So-Called “Astonished” Questions in Repair.” In Prosody in Conversation: Interactional Studies, ed. by Elizabeth Couper-Kuhlen and Margret Selting, 231–270. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ; Wilkinson and Kitzinger 2006Wilkinson, Sue, and Celia Kitzinger 2006 “Surprise as an Interactional Achievement: Reaction Tokens in Conversation.” Social Psychology Quarterly 69(2): 150–182. ). Maria has initiated a repair to address a problem of expectation rather than a problem of hearing or understanding (Couper-Kuhlen and Selting 2018Couper-Kuhlen, Elizabeth, and Margret Selting 2018 Interactional Linguistics: Studying Language in Social Interaction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press., 188), and conveys that what Ourania said in her prior turn is in contradiction to Maria’s knowledge or expectations about what is true or acceptable. In line 12, Ourania emphatically confirms with the marked particle ↑NE::: (‘yes’), delivered contiguously, with higher pitch, loudness, duration and in laughing mode. The polar answer provides the confirmation requested and demonstrates that the respondent treats herself as [K+] and the questioner as [K−]. That is, the polar answer accepts the epistemic terms of the question. At the same time, the marked response token embraces the surprise expressed by the questioner. The respondent mobilizes prosodic resources, such as higher pitch, loudness and duration, to convey a congruent evaluative stance. Compare for example the intonation contour in Figure 2, the unmarked token ne in Extract (1), with the intonation contour in Figure 3, the marked token ne in Extract (4).
In these examples, prosodic variation of the same response token serves to convey the respondent’s different evaluative/affective stance towards the question. In Extract (1), the unmarked response token does ‘simple’ and neutral answering, whereas in Extract (4), the prosodically marked response token does ‘affectively charged’ answering (for the role of prosody in conveying stance see e.g. Couper-Kuhlen 2009Couper-Kuhlen, Elizabeth 2009 “A Sequential Approach to Affect: The Case of Disappointment.” In Talk in Interaction: Comparative Dimensions, ed. by Markku Haakana, Minna Laakso, and Jan Lindström, 94–123. Helsinki: Finnish Literature Society.; Golato and Fagyal 2008Golato, Andrea, and Zsuzsanna Fagyal 2008 “Comparing Single and Double Sayings of the German Response Token Ja and the Role of Prosody: A Conversation Analytic Perspective.” Research on Language and Social Interaction 41(3): 241–270. ; Selting 1996Selting, Margret 1996 “Prosody as an Activity Type Distinctive Cue in Conversation: The Case of So-Called “Astonished” Questions in Repair.” In Prosody in Conversation: Interactional Studies, ed. by Elizabeth Couper-Kuhlen and Margret Selting, 231–270. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ; Wilkinson and Kitzinger 2006Wilkinson, Sue, and Celia Kitzinger 2006 “Surprise as an Interactional Achievement: Reaction Tokens in Conversation.” Social Psychology Quarterly 69(2): 150–182. ; Ward 2019Ward, Nigel 2019 Prosodic Patterns in English Conversation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. , among other).
Another example is in Extract (5). Chrysanthi has informed Ourania and Athina about changes in how domestic calls are made, and she mentions that callers need to dial zero with no extra charges.
1 Ath: -> ðila↑ðí:, θa bor- θa: ʝa na páro eɣό apό: that is fut can fut to sbjv call.1sg I from That ↑i:s, can- wi:ll in order to call o:n 2 -> kartotiléfono eséna stο staθerό su pre-paid phone you.sg to landline your.sg your landline fro:m a pre-paid phone 3 -> θa pérno miðén triáda éna <miðén?> = fut call.1sg zero thirty one zero do I need to dial zero thirty one <zero?> = 4 Chr: => = <Νe ne ne.> = yes yes yes = <Yes yes yes.> = 5 Our: => =Νe. yes =Yes.
After intervening talk and a gap, Athina initiates repair to check understanding of the information provided at a distance from the repair (Benjamin 2012Benjamin, Trevor 2012 “When Problems Pass Us By: Using “You Mean” to Help Locate the Source of Trouble.” Research on Language and Social Interaction 45(1): 82–109. ). In lines 1–3, the speaker offers a candidate understanding (inference) of the trouble source (‘in order to call o:n your landline fro:m a pre-paid phone do I need to dial zero thirty one <zero?>’). The repair initiator is a polar question that seeks confirmation and positions the questioner as [K−]. In lines 4–5, Chrysanthi and Ourania overtly confirm the questioner’s understanding with the marked response tokens <Νe ne ne.> (‘yes yes yes.’) and Νe (‘yes’), and demonstrate that they treat themselves as [K+]. Respondents answer immediately, without providing any further explanation or information in understanding the trouble source. That is, they treat the questioner’s candidate understanding as an affiliative move that does not create a serious obstacle to the progressivity of talk (e.g. because the questioner claims that she knows better) (Antaki 2012Antaki, Charles 2012 “Affiliative and Disaffiliative Candidate Understandings.” Discourse Studies 14(5): 531–547. ). Respondents mobilize prosodic resources, such as slowed speech rate and higher pitch, and repetition to emphatically confirm information that has been accurately inferred from prior talk, and affectively align with the questioner’s proffering of a candidate understanding.
Extract (6) comes from a telephone call between Dimitra and her granddaughter, Zina. After the greeting sequence, Zina initiates a new topic about the Easter holiday in lines 1–2, and Dimitra replies that they had a barbeque with Yorgakis and the kids in lines 3–4, 7. The question of interest is in line 9.
1 Ζin: °Νe:.° to Pásxa ↑pos ta pé:rases? yes def Easter how pn pass.2sg °Yes.° ↑How wa:s Easter? 2 írθe: ο: θíοs? come.3sg def uncle Did uncle come:? 3 Dim: Νe. ↑í:rθe ο Yorɣá:cis, (.) me ta peðʝá: όli, yes come.3sg def Yorgakis(m) with def kids all.m Yes. Yorga:kis ↑ca:me, (.) with the ki:ds all of them, 4 psísame eðό:, fáɣane, tο vrá:ði fíɣane. grill.1pl here eat.3pl def night leave.3pl we had a barberque here:, they ate, in the eve:ning they left. 5 (0.5) 6 Ζin: Α: [(όli-)] ah all.m O:h [(all-)] 7 Dim: [(Oréa)] perásame. polí kalá. well pass.1pl very well We had [(a good time).] Very good. 8 (0.6) 9 Ζin: -> Ítan ce ta peðʝá:? cop.3pl.pst and def kids Did the ki:ds come as well? 10 (.) 11 Dim: => >Vévea.< ό:li ítane. of course all.m cop.3pl.pst >Of course.< They all came. 12 Zin: °Μ.° ο Έksarxos ti ká:ni. particle def Eksarxos(m) what do.3sg ‘Mm. How is Eksarxos?’
After a gap (line 8), Zina launches a new sequence in line 9. She uses a polar question to ask whether the kids joined the barbeque, that is, to request information that Dimitra has already provided in line 3. After a micro-pause that indicates trouble (line 10), Dimitra confirms via the semantically emphatic adverb >vévea< (‘of course’) in line 11. The polar answer treats the questioner as [K−] and highlights the obviousness of the answer. In the next TCU, the respondent provides further explanation (‘they all came’), repeating information from her prior turn with emphasis, and, thus, she displays her problem with the necessity of the question. Zina closes down the sequence via the neutral information receipt token m in line 12.
In sum, speakers use marked positive response tokens to provide overt confirmations to polar questions. These overt confirmations accept the epistemic terms of the question and also address aspects of the derived action being implemented via the question, namely they convey a congruent evaluative stance towards ‘surprised’ repair initiation, affectively align with the proffering of a candidate understanding or highlight the obviousness of the answer.
3.3Repetition
When respondents seek to resist the questioner’s epistemic positioning and assert their own epistemic authority, they deploy repetition. This pattern is visible in (7):
1 Our: Ce >ksérete ti skéftome?< όti an válo ce and know.2pl what think.1sg that if put.1sg and And >do you know what I’m thinking?< That if I also use 2 staθerό, (.) e:: (0.7) ðen gzéro:, landline phone eh neg know.1sg a landline phone, (.) u::h (0.7) I don’t kno:w, 3 θa: íne pára polí ce to páʝio. fut cop.3sg.prs very much and def fixed rate the fixed rate wi:ll be very high as well. 4 ðilaðí >tο [páʝio] eména stο Réθimno that is def fixed rate pn in def Rethymno That is >in Rethymno the [fixed rate] 5 Αth: [°Νe. ] yes [°Yes.] 6 Οur: erxόtan οxtό çiʎáðes¿< = come.3sg eight thousand costed eight thousand¿< = 7 Αth: =Ks- [pόsο. eɣό páli (íç-)] how much I adv =How [much. I also (had-)] 8 Οur: [°(Tο ðímino.)° ΕΝO BORO [ΝΑ] pérno] def two months but can.1sg sbjv call.1sg [°(For two months).° BUT I CAN [call] 9 Chr: [°Ise síɣuri?] cop.2sg.prs sure.f.sg [°Are you sure?] 10 Our: °ne. pá[ʝio.] yes fixed rate °Yes. Fixed [rate.] 11 Chr: -> [ °Se] staθerό?= prep landline.n.acc.sg [°For] a landline phone?= 12 Our: => =↑Se staθerό.= prep landline.n.acc.sg =↑For a landline phone.= 13 Chr: =Τi lé[te ] re peðʝá what say.2pl particle guys =Hey guys, sa[y] what? 14 Our: [°Νe.] yes [°Yes.] 15 Chr: ce ðe mu éçi érθi lοɣarʝazmόs akόmi.= ((laughing............................)) and neg pn have.3sg come bill yet and I still haven’t received the bill.=
In lines 1–4 and 6, Ourania informs her interlocutors of landline phone charges, and in lines 9 and 11, Chrysanthi challenges Ourania’s claim via a series of polar questions. Ourania responds to Chrysanthi’s first disagreement (‘Are you sure?) with the unmarked token ne (‘yes’) in line 10. Chrysanthi treats the response as non-conforming with the exigencies of the question and delivers another disagreement (‘For a landline phone?’). Ourania responds with a modified repeat in line 12: she repeats the phrase se staθerό with sharp intonation rise and final falling intonation. The derived actions implemented by the polar questions in this exchange challenge the respondent’s epistemic authority and imply the questioner’s primary epistemic rights over the information at issue. The respondent uses repetition to confirm the proposition raised by the question and assert her epistemic authority with respect to the knowledge domain being addressed. That is, the repetitional answer resists the epistemic terms of the question.
Α similar case is in Extract (8). The segment is from a conversation among three male friends, Yorgos, Manos, and Dimosthenis. In the lines preceding this segment, Yorgos has quoted Milan Kundera’s claim that men do not conquer women anymore. Manos has prompted Yorgos to elaborate, and Yorgos provides more information in lines 1–2. The question of interest is in line 4.
1 Yor: [ðen a]ɣonízοde as púme ʝa káti. neg fight.3pl so to speak.1pl for something [They do not f]ight for anything so to speak. 2 °ðen ganun káti. neg do.3pl something °They do nothing. 3 (0.7) 4 Dim: -> Αftό enoí? this.n.acc.sg mean.3sg.prs Is this what he means? 5 Yor: => Αf[tό enoí.] this.n.acc.sg mean.3sg.prs Th[is is what he means.] 6 Μan: [Τi ðilaðí?] what that is [That is?]
Dimosthenis delivers a polar question with emphasis (‘Is this what he means?’) that challenges Yorgos’ understanding of Kundera’s claim, indexes a shallow K− to K+ epistemic gradient, and implies the questioner’s primary epistemic rights over the information at issue. In line 5, Yorgos responds with a modified repeat of the question: he replicates the phrase aftό enoí (‘This is what he means.’) with final falling intonation and no emphasis. The repetitional answer confirms the question’s proposition and asserts the respondent’s epistemic authority over the matter in question.
In Extracts (7) and (8), repetitional answers resist the questioner’s epistemic stance. A slightly different pattern is visible in Extract (9):
1 Pol: -> =Αléka θimáse pos íxame érθi Aleka remember.2sg.prs how have.1pl.pst come.pfv =Aleka do you remember how we came 2 eðό péra mɲa forá?= here over one time here once?= 3 Αle: => =Το θi↑máme. aftό θimíθika [tόra.] it remember.1sg.prs this remember.1sg.pst now =I re↑member. I [just] remembered it. 4 Pol: [Μe ti]:: with def The:: 5 fialticí istoría °me taftocínito? nightmare story with def car nightmare story °with the car? 6 (0.5) 7 Νas: Τi:? ↑ti éʝine. what what happen.3sg.pst Wha:t? ↑What happened?
In lines 1–2, Polychronis uses a polar question (‘Aleka do you remember how we came here once?’) to initiate an assisted story telling and implement a ‘reminiscence recognition solicit’ (Lerner 1992Lerner, Gene H. 1992 “Assisted Story Telling: Deploying Shared Knowledge as a Practical Matter.” Qualitative Sociology 15(3): 247–271. ). This kind of preface forecasts a possible story but does “not indicate who is meant to deliver it” (Lerner 1992Lerner, Gene H. 1992 “Assisted Story Telling: Deploying Shared Knowledge as a Practical Matter.” Qualitative Sociology 15(3): 247–271. , 255). In line 3, Aleka responds with recognition: she repeats the verb θi↑máme in first person singular, with emphasis and final falling intonation, and adds the anaphoric pronoun to. Polychronis adds an increment to his question (lines 4–5), Aleka does not step in as the storyteller (there is a gap in line 6) and Nasos uses a wh-question to express his acceptance of the prior speakers telling the story. In the lines following (omitted for space considerations), Polychronis begins the delivery of the story and Aleka ends up as a story consociate who actively participates in the story delivery. The assisted story preface delivered by Polychronis demonstrates shared knowledge with Aleka and positions the questioner as knowledgeable. Aleka uses repetition to confirm her capacity to know some element of information due to experience. In this segment, the question’s derived action makes the respondent’s epistemic authority interactionally relevant and invites the respondent to display shared epistemic access and agency. The respondent uses repetition to bring her authority over the particular information to focused attention and takes no issue with the questioner’s epistemic positioning.
To recapitulate, speakers use repetition to confirm the question’s proposition and assert their epistemic authority. Repetitional answers can be treated as resisting or non-resisting the questioner’s epistemic stance, depending on whether the action carried out by the question challenges or not the respondent’s primary epistemic rights with respect to the knowledge domain being addressed. Conclusions are in the next section.
4.Concluding remarks
Data analysis demonstrates that unmarked and marked positive response tokens, and repetitional answers are not randomly distributed in second position in polar question sequences in Greek conversation. The three formats are “alternative ways of filling” the same sequential position or slot (Couper Kuhlen and Selting 2018Couper-Kuhlen, Elizabeth, and Margret Selting 2018 Interactional Linguistics: Studying Language in Social Interaction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press., 544), as they carry different communicative import. Unmarked and marked response tokens accept the questioner’s epistemic stance in subtly different ways. Unmarked response tokens do ‘simple’ answering, whereas marked response tokens provide overt confirmations. By contrast, repetitional answers assert the respondent’s epistemic authority and are treated as resisting the questioner’s epistemic stance, if the action carried out by the question challenges the respondent’s primary epistemic rights over the matter in question. To sum up, the three formats convey the respondent’s different epistemic positioning towards the question and the action it implements.
Epistemic stance taking in polar answers in Greek conversation is shown to be a public interactional joint achievement, as the respondent reacts to the stance conveyed by the questioner in their prior turn. Moreover, epistemic stance taking is shown to be context-dependent and inference-based, as it emerges from the recurrent use of specific linguistic (lexical and prosodic) resources in responsive position.
How are patterns found in polar answers in Greek conversation similar to or different from patterns observed in other languages? As mentioned in Section 1.1, cross-linguistically interjections or response tokens simply answer polar questions, whereas repetitions do more than simple answering (Enfield et al. 2019Enfield, N. J., Tanya Stivers, Penelope Brown, Christina Englert, Katariina Harjunpää, Makoto Hayashi, Trine Heinemann, Gertie Hoymann, Tiina Keisanen, Mirka Rauniomaa, Chase Raymond, Federico Rossano, Kyung-Eun Yoon, Inge Zwitserlood, Stephen Levinson 2019 “Polar Answers.” Journal of Linguistics 55(2): 277–304. ). The analysis of the Greek data provides further evidence for this universal pattern. Greek speakers use response tokens to affirm or confirm the question’s proposition, and they use repeats to do more than simply affirming or confirming. Yet, the communicative import of polar answers is shown to be context-specific.
Similar to Russian and English (see e.g. Bolden 2016 2016 “A Simple Da?: Affirming Responses to Polar Questions in Russian Conversation.” Journal of Pragmatics 100: 40–58. and Stivers 2019 2019 “How we Manage Social Relationships through Answers to Questions: The Case of Interjections”. Discourse Processes 56(3): 191–209. , Section 1.1), in Greek conversation, speakers use upgraded response tokens to confirm information that is expected to be known by the questioner, and respond to surprised repair initiation. Marked response tokens accept the questioner’s epistemic stance but they also serve to highlight the obviousness of the answer or convey a congruent affective stance. Also, similar to English (see e.g. Heritage and Raymond 2012 2012 “Navigating Epistemic Landscapes: Acquiescence, Agency and Resistance in Responses to Polar Questions.” In Questions: Formal, Functional and Interactional Perspectives, ed. by Jan P. De Ruiter, 179–192. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. , Section 1.1), repetitional answers in Greek conversation assert the respondents’ epistemic authority and are heard as resisting the epistemic terms of the question. However, Greek repetitional answers are not always competitive, as in certain contexts they display shared epistemic access and agency and acquiesce to the epistemic terms of the question (a similar pattern is observed in Tzeltal, Enfield et al. 2019Enfield, N. J., Tanya Stivers, Penelope Brown, Christina Englert, Katariina Harjunpää, Makoto Hayashi, Trine Heinemann, Gertie Hoymann, Tiina Keisanen, Mirka Rauniomaa, Chase Raymond, Federico Rossano, Kyung-Eun Yoon, Inge Zwitserlood, Stephen Levinson 2019 “Polar Answers.” Journal of Linguistics 55(2): 277–304. , 297–299, Section 1.1).
This paper has analyzed affirming/confirming polar answers delivered via positive response tokens and repeats, and has demonstrated that epistemic stance is a central component of polar answers in Greek conversation. Further research on other types of polar answer, such as downgraded tokens, combination and transformative answers, will enhance our understanding of the epistemic work that speakers do with different linguistic resources in responsive position in question sequences in Greek conversation.
Acknowledgements
An earlier version of this paper was presented at the 16th International Pragmatics Conference in Hong Kong in 2019. I would like to thank participants in this event for their valuable feedback. I am indebted to two anonymous referees for their constructive comments that helped improve the manuscript. All remaining errors are my own.
Notes
References
Appendix A.Abbreviations
first person
second person
third person
accusative
adverb
copula
definite
future
masculine
neuter
negation
particle
perfective
plural
pronoun
preposition
present
past
singular
subjunctive
Appendix B.Transcription conventions
[ | point of onset of overlap |
] | point of end of overlap |
= | latching |
(0.8) | silence in tenths of a second |
(.) | micro-pause (less than 0.5 second) |
. | falling/final intonation |
? | rising intonation |
¿ | rise stronger than a comma but weaker than question mark |
, | continuing/non-final intonation |
: :: | sound prolongation or stretching; the more colons, the longer the stretching |
word | underlining is used to indicate some form of emphasis, either by increased loudness or higher pitch |
° | following talk markedly quiet or soft |
- | after a word or part of a word: cut-off or interruption |
↑ | sharp intonation rise |
> < | talk between the ‘more than’ and ‘less than’ symbols is compressed or rushed |
< > | talk between the ‘less than’ and ‘more than’ symbols is markedly slowed or drawn out |
h | hearable aspiration; its repetition indicates longer duration |
.hh | inhalation |
(( )) | transcriber’s description of events |
(word) | uncertain transcription |
(…) | unidentified syllables or segments |