Knowledge types and presuppositions: An analysis of strategic aspects of public apologies

Jocelyn A. S. Navera and Leah Gustilo

Abstract

Public apologies are so prevalent in our social lives that they have become a subject of scholarly investigation all over the globe. The present study, which involves coding, frequency counting, and qualitative analysis, examines the strategic aspects of 16 public apologies issued to Filipino apologizees. The results of our analysis indicate that apologizers often choose varied knowledge types and draw upon presuppositions to strategically omit details that can negatively influence their credibility and the reception of their apology. More specifically, apologizers use the audience’s presuppositions to avoid presenting common knowledge of the offense that may incriminate them further; they also omit the mention of future action that may hold them more accountable for their transgressions. Our present analysis bolsters the view that although the sincerity of public apologies cannot be exactly measured, they are still performed as part of image repair and management of interpersonal relationships.

Keywords:
Publication history
Table of contents

1.Introduction

In a world where social media reigns, every small action is documented. What was once private, only for those who are close enough to be privy to one’s littlest movements, is now public, where one’s remotest acquaintance can get a glimpse and even comment on any move one makes. It is no surprise then that apologies, which used to be interpersonal events that happen in the most private of spheres, have now gone public. From motorists who err on the highway to presidents who sin on the national stage, public apologies are even more relevant now than when they first became an important focus of investigation in the 1980s among discourse analysts and sociolinguists (Gonzalez-Cruz 2012Gonzalez-Cruz, Maria Isabel 2012 “Apologizing in Spanish: A Study of the Strategies Used by University Students in Las Palmas De Gran Canaria.” Pragmatics 22:543–565. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 543; Kampf 2013 2013 “The Discourse of Public Apologies: Modes of Realization, Interpretation and Mediation.” In Public Apology Between Ritual and Regret, ed. by Daniël Cuypers, Daniel Janssen, Jacques Haers, and Barbara Segaert, 145–165. Netherlands: Rodopi. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 148; Maclachlan 2015MacLachlan, Alice 2015 “ ‘Trust Me, I’m Sorry’: The Paradox of Public Apology.” The Monist 98 (4): 441–456. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Zhanghong and Li 2020Zhanghong, Xiu, and Yanan Li 2020 “A Pragmatic Study of Apologies Posted on Weibo by Chinese Celebrities.” International Journal of Literature and Arts 8 (2): 52–61. DOI logoGoogle Scholar).

Myers (2016)Myers, Cayce 2016 “Apology, Sympathy, and Empathy: The Legal Ramifications of Admitting Fault in U.S. Public Relations Practice.” Public Relations Review 42: 176–183. DOI logoGoogle Scholar has observed that the speech act of apology has become a ritual, and it is practiced across cultures (Ancarno 2015Ancarno, Clyde S. 2015 “When are Public Apologies ‘Successful’? Focus on British and French Apology Press Uptakes.” Journal of Pragmatics 84: 139–153. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Kampf 2013 2013 “The Discourse of Public Apologies: Modes of Realization, Interpretation and Mediation.” In Public Apology Between Ritual and Regret, ed. by Daniël Cuypers, Daniel Janssen, Jacques Haers, and Barbara Segaert, 145–165. Netherlands: Rodopi. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). Such observation is supported by a plethora of research on apologies that is rich in perspective and multicultural in scope (Marrus 2006Marrus, Michael R. 2006Official Apologies and the Quest for Historical Justice. Toronto: University of Toronto.Google Scholar; Nobles 2008Nobles, Melissa 2008 The Politics of Official Apologies . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Page 2014Page, Ruth 2014 “Saying ‘Sorry’: Corporate Apologies Posted on Twitter.” Journal of pragmatics 62: 30–45. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). Most of the work on apologies have employed the speech act theory (Austin 1962Austin, John 1962How to Do Things with Words. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar; Searle 1979Searle, John 1979Expression and Meaning: Studies in the Theory of Speech Acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar), the concept of face (Goffman 1967Goffman, Erving 1967Interaction Ritual: Essays on Face-to-face behavior. Garden City, NY: Doubleday.Google Scholar), remedial interchanges, and the politeness theory (Brown and Levinson 1987Brown, Penelope, and Stephen Levinson 1987Politeness: Some Universals in Language Usage (Studies in Interactional Sociolinguistics 4). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). From the time Austin (1962)Austin, John 1962How to Do Things with Words. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar proposed that words performed actions and Searle (1979)Searle, John 1979Expression and Meaning: Studies in the Theory of Speech Acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar modified the former’s categories, inquiries regarding apologies began. Coupled with Goffman’s (1967)Goffman, Erving 1967Interaction Ritual: Essays on Face-to-face behavior. Garden City, NY: Doubleday.Google Scholar concept of Face and its influence on our interactions and Brown and Levinson’s (1987)Brown, Penelope, and Stephen Levinson 1987Politeness: Some Universals in Language Usage (Studies in Interactional Sociolinguistics 4). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar work on apology as a face-threatening act, researchers from different parts of the globe have attempted to dig deeper into this social phenomenon. However, only a handful have focused on presuppositions in apologies (Blum-Kulka and Olshtain 1984Blum-Kulka, Shoshana, and Elite Olshtain 1984 “Requests and Apologies: A Cross-cultural Study of Speech Act Realization Patterns (CCSARP).” Applied Linguistics 5: 196–213. DOI logoGoogle Scholar), which is one of the gaps that this present study aims to fill.

In the local setting, our survey of the literature on this topic reveals that only three studies have investigated Filipino apologies. Mojica (2004Mojica, Leonisa 2004 “Apology Strategies Perceived to be Appropriate by Filipino-speaking Couples.” Philippine Journal of Linguistics 34: 27–40.Google Scholar, 35) highlighted the usefulness of apologies in doing repair, in affirming a person’s self-worth, in meeting a person’s face needs, and in mending ruined interpersonal relationships between Filipino couples. Oclaret (2013)Oclaret, Venjie N. 2013 “Apology Strategies of Filipino and Filipino-Chinese Third Year High School Students.” (Unpublished research paper) Philippine Normal University–Manila, Manila, Philippines.Google Scholar compared the apology strategies used by Filipino and Filipino-Chinese senior students and found that the latter have fewer apology strategies. De La Rosa and Castro (2016)De La Rosa, John Paul O., and Lorna B. Castro 2016 “Is It Too Late Now to Say Sorry? The Language of Public Apologies in the Contexts of American and Philippine Television.” i-manager’s Journal on English Language Teaching 6: 29–44. DOI logoGoogle Scholar did a cross-cultural analysis of public apologies issued by American and Filipino television hosts and observed that the Filipino TV host resorted to self-justification and evasive language to deny responsibility for the offense. These investigations have unearthed a number of strategies, realizations, and functions of apologies in the Philippine setting. An analysis of the strategic aspects of public apologies, more specifically the types of knowledge used during the act of apologizing and the role of presuppositions in making apologies, will reveal the kind of background knowledge apologizers assume their audience has. It is hoped that this investigation will be an addition to the body of research that can help increase the understanding of this ritual of image repair not just within the Philippine context, but also across different cultures.

The present study makes use of categorization, frequency counts, and qualitative description of the strategic link between knowledge types and presuppositions in public apologies issued to Filipino apologizees. Public apologies here refer to apologies made by individuals or groups in a public setting (such as on social media and television), while the Philippine context covers the involvement of any Filipino in the apology, either as the apology giver or receiver. In sum, this present study aims to answer the following research questions:

  1. Which knowledge types are commonly used in the selected public apologies?

  2. What type of information is left unsaid or presupposed regarding the Act (transgression) done and future actions to be taken to atone for the Act?

2.Theoretical and empirical backgrounds

The present study interweaves previous works on presupposition, knowledge types, and the speech act of apology in order to underpin its analysis. The definition and linguistic cues of presupposition are discussed first; it is followed by the discussion on knowledge types according to Van Dijk (2000Van Dijk, Teun A. 2000 “Cognitive Discourse Analysis.” March 10 2021 http://​www​.discursos​.org​/unpublished%20articles​/cogn​-dis​-anal​.htm, 2004 2004 “Knowledge and News.” Revista Canaria de Estudios Ingleses 49:71–86.) and Bekalu’s (2006)Bekalu, Mesfin A. 2006 “Presupposition in News Discourse.” Discourse & Society 17: 147–172. DOI logoGoogle Scholar application of Van Dijk’s knowledge types in documenting the nexus between knowledge types and presupposition. The last section focuses on the theoretical and empirical underpinnings of the speech act of apology.

2.1Presupposition

Presupposition is defined as a proposition or an inference that is taken for granted. It serves as a precondition (Huang 2007Huang, Yan 2007Pragmatics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar), mutual knowledge (Levinson, 1983Levinson, Stephen C. 1983Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar), background knowledge (Yule 2006Yule, George 2006The Study of Language (3rd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar, 112), or common ground (Stalnaker 2002Stalnaker, Robert C. 2002 “Pragmatic Presupposition.” In Pragmatics: Critical Concepts, Vol. IV: Presupposition, Implicature and Indirect Speech Acts, ed. by Asa Kasher, 46–62. London: Routledge.Google Scholar) for the interlocutor’s appropriate interpretation of an utterance or a sentence. Hence, when someone is presupposing something, that person is assuming something or taking it for granted. In other words, presupposition is the preparatory knowledge which acts as a common starting point for communication between the speaker and the hearer. The meaning of what is said (explicit information) rests on what is unsaid (implicit presupposition). The writer/speaker decides what to say explicitly and what to leave the audience to assume. Hence, presupposition directs the interlocutors in the selection and interpretation of information (Saarinen 2008Saarinen, Tania 2008 “Persuasive Presuppositions in OECD and EU Higher Education Policy Documents.” Discourse Studies 10: 341–359. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 345).

However, Saarinen (2008Saarinen, Tania 2008 “Persuasive Presuppositions in OECD and EU Higher Education Policy Documents.” Discourse Studies 10: 341–359. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 345) opines that it is not proper to believe that speakers and hearers always share the same background knowledge or presupposition. The writer or speaker may be communicating to a split audience, with some sharing the writer’s/speaker’s assumptions while others do not (Sbisà, 1999Sbisà, Marina 1999 “Ideology and the Persuasive Use of Presupposition.” In Language and Ideology: Selected Papers from the 6th International Pragmatics Conference Vol. 1, ed. by Jef Verschueren, 492–509. Antwerp: International Pragmatics Association.Google Scholar). Such a case triggers the speaker or writer to give new information as something that is presupposed (Saarinen 2008Saarinen, Tania 2008 “Persuasive Presuppositions in OECD and EU Higher Education Policy Documents.” Discourse Studies 10: 341–359. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Sbisà 1999Sbisà, Marina 1999 “Ideology and the Persuasive Use of Presupposition.” In Language and Ideology: Selected Papers from the 6th International Pragmatics Conference Vol. 1, ed. by Jef Verschueren, 492–509. Antwerp: International Pragmatics Association.Google Scholar).

Giving new information as something assumed or presupposed has some benefits. The information may be accepted without criticism because it is implicitly communicated and not explicitly stated. In addition, presuppositions may lend support to the presentation of ideological assumptions as either common knowledge or hiding a value system and standpoints that may be opposed when expressed explicitly (Saarinen 2008Saarinen, Tania 2008 “Persuasive Presuppositions in OECD and EU Higher Education Policy Documents.” Discourse Studies 10: 341–359. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). Hence, presuppositions have a persuasive function as they can be regarded as a potent tool for communicating new information or common knowledge about values and ideologies in an implicit way (Papi 2003Papi, Marcella B. 2003 “Implicitness.” In Handbook of Pragmatics Online, ed. by Jan-Ola Östman and Jef Verschueren, Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI logoGoogle Scholar).

Presupposition has linguistic devices called presupposition triggers, which give cues to the readers/listeners (Huang 2007Huang, Yan 2007Pragmatics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar; Levinson 1983Levinson, Stephen C. 1983Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). These presupposition triggers aid the readers /listeners in the interpretation of an utterance. For example, in “[t]he king of France is/isn’t bald” (Huang 2007Huang, Yan 2007Pragmatics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar), the use of definite description or existential presupposition enables the readers to presuppose that France has a king. Other presupposition triggers are factive predicates (e.g. know, regret), aspectual/change of state predicates (e.g. stop), iterative verbs (e.g. return), iterative adjectives (e.g. again), implicative predicates (e.g. manage), temporal clauses (e.g. After she did it…), cleft sentences (e.g. It was/wasn’t Baird who invented television), and counterfactual conditionals (Huang 2007Huang, Yan 2007Pragmatics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar).

Theoretical studies on presupposition abound in linguistics (Beaver 2001Beaver, David I. 2001Presupposition and Assertion in Dynamic Semantics. Stanford: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar; Huang 2007Huang, Yan 2007Pragmatics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar; Levinson 1983Levinson, Stephen C. 1983Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). However, empirical studies on presupposition are sparse. One of these studies is Saarinen’s (2008)Saarinen, Tania 2008 “Persuasive Presuppositions in OECD and EU Higher Education Policy Documents.” Discourse Studies 10: 341–359. DOI logoGoogle Scholar investigation of the persuasiveness of the higher education policies of Organization for Economic Co-operation and Development (OECD) and the European Union (EU). The study revolves around three focal points: the kind of information that is presupposed in the policies, the kinds of persuasive features the presuppositions represent, and the kind of ideology the presuppositions create. Three policies from OECD and three from the EU are selected. Only the introduction sections that focus on the concept of ‘quality’ are analyzed. Texts with no mention of quality are not included in the study. The first part of the investigation uses Levinson’s (1983)Levinson, Stephen C. 1983Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar presupposition triggers but focuses only on existentials, factives, change of state verbs, and temporals. Top findings of Saarinen’s study indicate that the persuasiveness of the policies’ presuppositions is not argumentative in nature. Instead, presuppositions help in depicting quality in higher education as a phenomenon that already exists. Had these evaluations of quality been explicitly argued, the assertions would have been open to challenge and scrutiny. Saarinen (2008)Saarinen, Tania 2008 “Persuasive Presuppositions in OECD and EU Higher Education Policy Documents.” Discourse Studies 10: 341–359. DOI logoGoogle Scholar concludes that presupposition promises more persuasive powers than explicit avowals do.

2.2Presupposition and knowledge types

Another empirical study on presupposition is Bekalu’s (2006)Bekalu, Mesfin A. 2006 “Presupposition in News Discourse.” Discourse & Society 17: 147–172. DOI logoGoogle Scholar work on news discourse. Bekalu analyzes the presupposed knowledge types in news discourse in selected Ethiopian Newspapers written in English. The investigation determines whether or not the presupposed information is fair or unfair and whether it is used for ideological purposes. The study is underpinned by a combination of frameworks: Van Dijk’s 2000Van Dijk, Teun A. 2000 “Cognitive Discourse Analysis.” March 10 2021 http://​www​.discursos​.org​/unpublished%20articles​/cogn​-dis​-anal​.htm and 2004 2004 “Knowledge and News.” Revista Canaria de Estudios Ingleses 49:71–86. works on the typology of knowledge and presuppositions as part of Cognitive Discourse Analysis and Sperber and Wilson’s (1995) 1995Relevance: Communication & Cognition. 2nd ed. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar Relevance Theory (RT).

In his article “Cognitive Discourse Analysis,” Van Dijk (2000)Van Dijk, Teun A. 2000 “Cognitive Discourse Analysis.” March 10 2021 http://​www​.discursos​.org​/unpublished%20articles​/cogn​-dis​-anal​.htm defines presuppositions as “a set of meaning conditions of a sentence: what we must know in order to understand a sentence (or sequence of sentences)” (33). These presuppositions are further supported by “expressions in the text” that “signal” them (Van Dijk, 2000Van Dijk, Teun A. 2000 “Cognitive Discourse Analysis.” March 10 2021 http://​www​.discursos​.org​/unpublished%20articles​/cogn​-dis​-anal​.htm). As an example, Van Dijk (2000)Van Dijk, Teun A. 2000 “Cognitive Discourse Analysis.” March 10 2021 http://​www​.discursos​.org​/unpublished%20articles​/cogn​-dis​-anal​.htm uses the statement “even the terrorists took pity on the victims” and explains that the word “even” reveals a presupposition about the usual behavior of the terrorists, which is “pitiless” or the opposite of taking pity on others. He believes that these types of presuppositions in news discourse become controversial when the suggested propositions in the presupposition are assumed to be true when, in fact, they are not. Van Dijk (2004) 2004 “Knowledge and News.” Revista Canaria de Estudios Ingleses 49:71–86., in a paper that solely focuses on news discourse, stresses the importance of this kind of knowledge management as part of continuous information modification in the public sphere. One of the headings clearly states his position: “No News Without Knowledge” (71). His main preoccupation in this paper is to examine what kind and how much knowledge is given and received in news presentations. For example, he claims that journalists modify their audience’s knowledge through reports, and it is crucial for journalists to assume just how much their audience knows. He notes the influence of built mental models in how news is perceived by the audience and that, typically, journalists only need to provide information that the audience does not have yet; the rest of the work is done by the existing mental models the audience has gathered from previous world knowledge. However, he bemoans the lack of explicit categorization of the types of knowledge that can help in the method of processing and analyzing discourses.

Because of this deficiency, Van Dijk (2005 2005 “Contextual Knowledge Management in Discourse Production: A CDA Perspective.” In A New Agenda in (Critical) Discourse Analysis: Theory, Methodology and Interdisciplinarity, ed. by Ruth Wodak and Paul Chilton, 71–100. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 73) has outlined six criteria providing categories by which types of knowledge can be characterized: Scope, Specificity, Concreteness, Reality, Objects, and Firmness. Scope includes six subtypes of knowledge, namely: Personal, Interpersonal, Group, Institutional, National, and Cultural. Bekalu (2006Bekalu, Mesfin A. 2006 “Presupposition in News Discourse.” Discourse & Society 17: 147–172. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 150) has used these knowledge types to determine the types of knowledge presupposed in the articles he analyzed.

To support Van Dijk’s categorization of knowledge types, Bekalu (2006)Bekalu, Mesfin A. 2006 “Presupposition in News Discourse.” Discourse & Society 17: 147–172. DOI logoGoogle Scholar uses Relevance Theory (Sperber and Wilson 1995 1995Relevance: Communication & Cognition. 2nd ed. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar) to examine the amount of cognitive processing effort expended by the readers in activating the presupposed background knowledge. By analyzing five news articles written in English and published in three Ethiopian newspapers, he concludes that the number and quality of presuppositions that the audience forms dictate how open they are to receiving the news content. Bekalu (2006)Bekalu, Mesfin A. 2006 “Presupposition in News Discourse.” Discourse & Society 17: 147–172. DOI logoGoogle Scholar has claimed that most Ethiopian newspaper readers do not want to invest time sifting through content that requires them to presuppose information that they have to ascertain or accept as true; they want to get information through the most accessible and acceptable language possible. And since these Ethiopian readers are more comfortable with their native language, Amharic, the additional hurdle of English discourages them from seeing the news as relevant to them. On the other hand, although English-speaking expatriates living in Ethiopia have a better grasp of these English-language news articles, they do not have the necessary background knowledge or context to make sense of the new information. In Bekalu’s (2006)Bekalu, Mesfin A. 2006 “Presupposition in News Discourse.” Discourse & Society 17: 147–172. DOI logoGoogle Scholar analyses, the types of knowledge invoked in the articles are, more often than not, socio-political and specific regional/national knowledge types that English-speaking expatriates most likely do not possess. Bekalu’s (2006)Bekalu, Mesfin A. 2006 “Presupposition in News Discourse.” Discourse & Society 17: 147–172. DOI logoGoogle Scholar study has documented that certain types of knowledge are unfairly presupposed in discourse, obscuring issues for political and ideological reasons – a finding that is corroborated by Saarinen’s (2008Saarinen, Tania 2008 “Persuasive Presuppositions in OECD and EU Higher Education Policy Documents.” Discourse Studies 10: 341–359. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 344) statements and further bolstered by the analysis in the present study.

2.3The speech act of apology

It has been claimed that the current society lives in an “Age of Apology” (Kampf 2013 2013 “The Discourse of Public Apologies: Modes of Realization, Interpretation and Mediation.” In Public Apology Between Ritual and Regret, ed. by Daniël Cuypers, Daniel Janssen, Jacques Haers, and Barbara Segaert, 145–165. Netherlands: Rodopi. DOI logoGoogle Scholar) due to the robust production of research on this field. Starting from Austin’s (1962)Austin, John 1962How to Do Things with Words. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar seminal work on speech acts up to the present, most especially in the last 20 years, studies on apologies have been quite ubiquitous (Harris, Grainger, and Mullany 2006Harris, Sandra, Karen Grainger, and Louise Mullany 2006 “The Pragmatics of Political Apologies.” Discourse & Society 17: 715–737. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Kampf 2013 2013 “The Discourse of Public Apologies: Modes of Realization, Interpretation and Mediation.” In Public Apology Between Ritual and Regret, ed. by Daniël Cuypers, Daniel Janssen, Jacques Haers, and Barbara Segaert, 145–165. Netherlands: Rodopi. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Weyeneth 2001Weyeneth, Robert R. 2001 “The Power of Apology and the Process of Historical Reconciliation.” The Public Historian 23 (3): 9–38. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). The perspectives, definitions, and propositions have been vast, and the studies cited in this paper are but the most recent work on public apologies. One of the most notable works of recent times is Zhanghong and Li’s (2020Zhanghong, Xiu, and Yanan Li 2020 “A Pragmatic Study of Apologies Posted on Weibo by Chinese Celebrities.” International Journal of Literature and Arts 8 (2): 52–61. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 52–61) investigation on the apologies of Chinese celebrities posted on Weibo, a Chinese micro-blogging site. Drawing on Blum-Kulka and Olshtain’s (1984)Blum-Kulka, Shoshana, and Elite Olshtain 1984 “Requests and Apologies: A Cross-cultural Study of Speech Act Realization Patterns (CCSARP).” Applied Linguistics 5: 196–213. DOI logoGoogle Scholar Cross Cultural Speech Act Realization Patterns (CCSARP), they observe that Chinese celebrities frequently use IFID (Illocutionary Force Indicating Device) and “Explanations” or “Accounts” as the most common strategies in apologies and that they rarely use “Offer of Repair.” In their effort to restore their image and offset bad impressions, Chinese celebrities utilize “Mortification and Reduce Offensiveness.” As regards the types of IFID they use, “Being shamed or being embarrassed” (“羞愧”), “self-examination” (“反省”), and other mitigating tools unique only to Chinese culture are used. Zhanghong and Li’s (2020)Zhanghong, Xiu, and Yanan Li 2020 “A Pragmatic Study of Apologies Posted on Weibo by Chinese Celebrities.” International Journal of Literature and Arts 8 (2): 52–61. DOI logoGoogle Scholar investigation is an important documentation that sheds light on Chinese image management in the context of social media.

Another notable work is Murphy’s (2015)Murphy, James 2015 “Revisiting the Apology as a Speech Act: The Case of Parliamentary Apologies.” Journal of Language and Politics 14: 175–204. DOI logoGoogle Scholar “Revisiting the apology as a speech act.” In this study, he analyzes the case of UK parliamentary apologies, something that has been examined by previous researchers. What differentiates this particular article is its reexamination and redefinition of the speech act of apology. Murphy (2015)Murphy, James 2015 “Revisiting the Apology as a Speech Act: The Case of Parliamentary Apologies.” Journal of Language and Politics 14: 175–204. DOI logoGoogle Scholar mentions the Cross-Cultural Speech Act Realization Patterns (CCSARP) project by Blum-Kulka and Olshtain in 1984Blum-Kulka, Shoshana, and Elite Olshtain 1984 “Requests and Apologies: A Cross-cultural Study of Speech Act Realization Patterns (CCSARP).” Applied Linguistics 5: 196–213. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, which he attempts to modify given the occurrence of apologies that do not fit felicity conditions outlined in the project. Murphy (2015)Murphy, James 2015 “Revisiting the Apology as a Speech Act: The Case of Parliamentary Apologies.” Journal of Language and Politics 14: 175–204. DOI logoGoogle Scholar points to Searle and Vanderveken’s (1985Searle, John, and Daniel Vanderveken 1985Foundations of Illocutionary Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar, 176) definition of apology, which is, “if a speaker apologizes for something it must be for something that he [sic] has done or is otherwise responsible for,” along with Ogiermann’s (2009Ogiermann, Eva 2009On Apologising in Negative and Positive Politeness Cultures. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 176) propositional content of an apology that states that it should be a past action done by a speaker. Murphy (2015Murphy, James 2015 “Revisiting the Apology as a Speech Act: The Case of Parliamentary Apologies.” Journal of Language and Politics 14: 175–204. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 178) rejects both of these propositions, claiming that a person only needs to be indirectly responsible for an act done “to be able to felicitously apologi[z]e for it.” He also adds that apologies can be given in advance, and the action being apologized for does not necessarily have to be in the past (Murphy 2015Murphy, James 2015 “Revisiting the Apology as a Speech Act: The Case of Parliamentary Apologies.” Journal of Language and Politics 14: 175–204. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 182). In summary, he presents a new set of felicity conditions for apologies, which are the following:

Propositional content:

An act done, or to be done in the future, by the speaker or someone for whom the speaker is a formally recogni[z]ed representative.

Preparatory condition:

Speaker believes that the apology recipient, or a contextually relevant third party, believes that the act was an offence against the recipient (or someone whom the recipient represents).

Sincerity condition:

Speaker regrets the act or one of its consequences

Essential condition:

Utterance counts as an apology.

Boyd (2011Boyd, David P. 2011 “Art and Artifice in Public Apologies.” Journal of Business Ethics 104: 299–309. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 301) has also taken the redefinition of apology to another level by enumerating seven sequential components of an artful apology which are the following: Revelation (Explanation), Recognition (Empathy), Responsiveness (Timeliness), Responsibility (Internal Attribution), Remorse (Guilt), Restitution (Compensation), and Reform (Change). He also includes the other side of these components, which are Evasion, Estrangement, Tardiness, External Attribution, Guile, Abrogation, and Complacency. To see if these components are present in apologies, Boyd (2011)Boyd, David P. 2011 “Art and Artifice in Public Apologies.” Journal of Business Ethics 104: 299–309. DOI logoGoogle Scholar has analyzed seven well-publicized apologies, and he has been able to show that there is a pattern in their construction of apologies. Even though this present study does not make use of these sequential components, some of Boyd’s (2011)Boyd, David P. 2011 “Art and Artifice in Public Apologies.” Journal of Business Ethics 104: 299–309. DOI logoGoogle Scholar observations contribute to the analysis of the present data, specifically his points on Revelation (that apologizers often choose to evade rather than explain), Responsibility (that apologizers can admit their own faults, put the blame on other factors, or apologize for something other than the actual transgression), and Remorse (that apologizers can either show guilt or use guile to veil their misbehavior).

The work of Myers (2016)Myers, Cayce 2016 “Apology, Sympathy, and Empathy: The Legal Ramifications of Admitting Fault in U.S. Public Relations Practice.” Public Relations Review 42: 176–183. DOI logoGoogle Scholar corroborates Boyd’s (2011)Boyd, David P. 2011 “Art and Artifice in Public Apologies.” Journal of Business Ethics 104: 299–309. DOI logoGoogle Scholar analysis in that it also exhibits some of the latter’s assertions and shows public apologies in action via the political stage. Based on his analysis of US federal and state laws and evidentiary issues, Myers (2016)Myers, Cayce 2016 “Apology, Sympathy, and Empathy: The Legal Ramifications of Admitting Fault in U.S. Public Relations Practice.” Public Relations Review 42: 176–183. DOI logoGoogle Scholar regards apology as “taking responsibility” (176). He specifically talks about the aptly named “I’m sorry” laws – laws that exempt types of apology statements from being used as proof of guilt during trials. These emphasize both the creativity and the restrictions concerned in crafting an apology. Myers (2016)Myers, Cayce 2016 “Apology, Sympathy, and Empathy: The Legal Ramifications of Admitting Fault in U.S. Public Relations Practice.” Public Relations Review 42: 176–183. DOI logoGoogle Scholar draws on Coombs and Holladay (2008)Coombs, Timothy, and Sherry Holladay 2008 “Comparing Apology to Equivalent Crisis Response Strategies: Clarifying Apology’s Role and Value in Crisis Communication.” Public Relations Review 34: 252–257. DOI logoGoogle Scholar who argue that partial apology may be just what is needed in some situations. Most importantly, he acknowledges that apology is risky and may not be a cure-all for public relations crises.

In his study of 345 Israeli apologies, Kampf (2009)Kampf, Zohar 2009 “Public (non-)apologies: The Discourse of Minimizing Responsibility.” Journal of Pragmatics 41: 2257–2270. DOI logoGoogle Scholar echoes Coombs and Holladay’s (2008)Coombs, Timothy, and Sherry Holladay 2008 “Comparing Apology to Equivalent Crisis Response Strategies: Clarifying Apology’s Role and Value in Crisis Communication.” Public Relations Review 34: 252–257. DOI logoGoogle Scholar sentiments. He views apology as a tool for the restoration of one’s image even though it is a face threatening act that humiliates the apologizer and lessens their symbolic power. Kampf (2009)Kampf, Zohar 2009 “Public (non-)apologies: The Discourse of Minimizing Responsibility.” Journal of Pragmatics 41: 2257–2270. DOI logoGoogle Scholar also agrees with previous studies regarding the importance of acknowledgment, which goes hand in hand with an Illocutionary Force-Indicating Device (IFID) in creating an ideal apology. Because of this, it becomes tricky for political players who get involved in a conflict or controversy since they are made to choose between restoring public image or maintaining socio-political clout.

Hence, Kampf (2009)Kampf, Zohar 2009 “Public (non-)apologies: The Discourse of Minimizing Responsibility.” Journal of Pragmatics 41: 2257–2270. DOI logoGoogle Scholar opines that there is a negotiation between the apologizer and the apologizee. He points to a few strategies used by an offender to minimize responsibility and achieve one’s end. The first is the use of evasive or equivocal language. Its use may pacify some recipients of the apology without having to increase the risk the apologizer faces. Another common tactic is the non-performative apology. Kampf (2009)Kampf, Zohar 2009 “Public (non-)apologies: The Discourse of Minimizing Responsibility.” Journal of Pragmatics 41: 2257–2270. DOI logoGoogle Scholar defines this type of apology as not consisting of an active verb. He further divides this into three categories: (1) expression of willingness or duty to apologize, (2) promise to apologize, and (3) reference to past act of apologizing. He states that although these violate Grice’s maxim of manner, they protect the offender from full-blown negative consequences. Lastly, and perhaps most significantly, given that the current study deals with presuppositions, Kampf (2009Kampf, Zohar 2009 “Public (non-)apologies: The Discourse of Minimizing Responsibility.” Journal of Pragmatics 41: 2257–2270. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 2266–2267) enumerates linguistic terms that apologizers use to mask the offense and omit the exact nature of the wrong, and these are incident, hurt/harm/damage, words, mistake, and about that. The present study draws upon Kampf’s (2009)Kampf, Zohar 2009 “Public (non-)apologies: The Discourse of Minimizing Responsibility.” Journal of Pragmatics 41: 2257–2270. DOI logoGoogle Scholar aforementioned framework as the present findings also affirm that nomenclature makes a definitive impact on the production and reception of apologies.

Another study that aligns with Kampf’s (2009)Kampf, Zohar 2009 “Public (non-)apologies: The Discourse of Minimizing Responsibility.” Journal of Pragmatics 41: 2257–2270. DOI logoGoogle Scholar observations on cautious language is Bentley’s (2015)Bentley, Joshua M. 2015 “Shifting Identification: A Theory of Apologies and Pseudo-apologies.” Public Relations Review 41: 22–29. DOI logoGoogle Scholar study which posits that the apologizer goes a step further than evading responsibility and strategically shifts the blame to other parties, such as victims, fellow offenders, and even third-party observers. Using balance theory and co-orientation theory, he notes that offenders can minimize their participation through identification and division/dissociation. For example, an apologizer does not have to directly apologize for the offensive act; he can simply dissociate himself from it by saying it was not him, or he was not in his right frame of mind. He can also create this division from the act by dissociating with people who are identified with it. Here, the pseudo-apology can achieve the effect of image repair because it allows the offender to convince the audience that he and the act are separate entities.

Finally, studies by Ancarno (2015)Ancarno, Clyde S. 2015 “When are Public Apologies ‘Successful’? Focus on British and French Apology Press Uptakes.” Journal of Pragmatics 84: 139–153. DOI logoGoogle Scholar and Kampf (2013) 2013 “The Discourse of Public Apologies: Modes of Realization, Interpretation and Mediation.” In Public Apology Between Ritual and Regret, ed. by Daniël Cuypers, Daniel Janssen, Jacques Haers, and Barbara Segaert, 145–165. Netherlands: Rodopi. DOI logoGoogle Scholar deal with the reception of public apologies, specifically with how the media plays a role in how the offender and his words are perceived by the spectating public. Ancarno’s (2015Ancarno, Clyde S. 2015 “When are Public Apologies ‘Successful’? Focus on British and French Apology Press Uptakes.” Journal of Pragmatics 84: 139–153. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 139) work likens apologies to “politeness in the public sphere” and foregrounds the comments of news writers on political public apologies. He focuses on the explicit evaluative statements showing the news writers’ perspectives on apologies (Hunston and Thompson as cited in Ancarno, 2015Ancarno, Clyde S. 2015 “When are Public Apologies ‘Successful’? Focus on British and French Apology Press Uptakes.” Journal of Pragmatics 84: 139–153. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). Although the focus is on the reactions to the apologies, Ancarno (2015)Ancarno, Clyde S. 2015 “When are Public Apologies ‘Successful’? Focus on British and French Apology Press Uptakes.” Journal of Pragmatics 84: 139–153. DOI logoGoogle Scholar reiterates Kampf (2009)Kampf, Zohar 2009 “Public (non-)apologies: The Discourse of Minimizing Responsibility.” Journal of Pragmatics 41: 2257–2270. DOI logoGoogle Scholar in saying that wording is important to an apology’s success in order to regain the reputation of the apologizer. What is unique in Ancarno’s (2015)Ancarno, Clyde S. 2015 “When are Public Apologies ‘Successful’? Focus on British and French Apology Press Uptakes.” Journal of Pragmatics 84: 139–153. DOI logoGoogle Scholar research is that he mentions the media’s vital role in either supporting or criticizing apologies, which would then influence how it is disseminated to the public. Most importantly, Ancarno (2015)Ancarno, Clyde S. 2015 “When are Public Apologies ‘Successful’? Focus on British and French Apology Press Uptakes.” Journal of Pragmatics 84: 139–153. DOI logoGoogle Scholar acknowledges the cross-cultural presence of apologies that ultimately have a bearing on how an apology is viewed and consequently received.

Kampf’s (2013) 2013 “The Discourse of Public Apologies: Modes of Realization, Interpretation and Mediation.” In Public Apology Between Ritual and Regret, ed. by Daniël Cuypers, Daniel Janssen, Jacques Haers, and Barbara Segaert, 145–165. Netherlands: Rodopi. DOI logoGoogle Scholar observations are similar to Ancarno’s (2015)Ancarno, Clyde S. 2015 “When are Public Apologies ‘Successful’? Focus on British and French Apology Press Uptakes.” Journal of Pragmatics 84: 139–153. DOI logoGoogle Scholar in that even though the former’s data source is different, for it concentrates on Israeli press-reported apology-related utterances from 1997 to 2004, he takes the view that the speech act of apology is a social drama wherein the media dilutes the force of public speech acts. He specifies that the media presence in a public apology appears in different stages and has different effects. The media can play the role of an adjudicator in these special instances, instead of merely being vehicles of information. Next, the media can assert its belongingness to society by contributing to (perhaps a short-lived) social harmony. Media outlets are able to exercise a manipulative arm under the public’s nose because they can position themselves as being part of the public that they are attempting to influence. Lastly, the sensational nature of public apologies acts as fodder for the spectators; hence, they benefit the media by generating widespread interest. It is known that the media gains its power from the breadth of their reach; therefore, the “social drama” of apology is only effective when it has a wide fanbase that follows every chapter of the story. Kampf (2013) 2013 “The Discourse of Public Apologies: Modes of Realization, Interpretation and Mediation.” In Public Apology Between Ritual and Regret, ed. by Daniël Cuypers, Daniel Janssen, Jacques Haers, and Barbara Segaert, 145–165. Netherlands: Rodopi. DOI logoGoogle Scholar then makes the point that the media takes a representative role and, on behalf of the public, questions apologies and their sincerity. This adds another layer of nuance to the process of crafting an apology that is made to appease those directly and indirectly affected by it.

In pursuing the view of apologies as a social drama, Cels (2015)Cels, Sanderijn 2015 “Interpreting Political Apologies: The Neglected Role of Performance.” Political Psychology 36: 351–360. DOI logoGoogle Scholar adds that the performance of the apology itself is often neglected and that, in fact, dramaturgy can also matter to those the apology is directed to and to those who witness the apology. Dramaturgy here refers to the setting up of the scene, the division of roles, and the acting of players in the play or drama. Cels (2015)Cels, Sanderijn 2015 “Interpreting Political Apologies: The Neglected Role of Performance.” Political Psychology 36: 351–360. DOI logoGoogle Scholar proposes that the analysis of the apology be expanded to how the “stage” for the apology is set since it adds meaning to the apology and how it is perceived. He further justifies this perspective by highlighting the fact that apologies are not taken out of context and, therefore, should never be analyzed without the contextual factors.

Supplementing this expansion of the scope of analysis on apology is Towner’s (2010)Towner, Emil B. 2010 “Truly Public Apologies: Third-party Participation in Rwandan Apologetic Rhetoric.” Qualitative Research Reports in Communication 11: 63–69. DOI logoGoogle Scholar work on Rwandan Apologetic Rhetoric, which situates the participation of third parties as another aspect that is overlooked. Towner (2010)Towner, Emil B. 2010 “Truly Public Apologies: Third-party Participation in Rwandan Apologetic Rhetoric.” Qualitative Research Reports in Communication 11: 63–69. DOI logoGoogle Scholar states that this is so because apologies are often studied using the Western lens, and this approach takes for granted that different social and cultural dynamics can also cause differences in apologetic rhetoric. In his work, he positions third-party participants as not just witnesses, but also as mediators, evaluators, and even offenders, depending on the context of the apology. The highly collective nature of Rwandan society foregrounds the impact of cultural values in the cause, delivery, and acceptance or rejection of public apologies.

Finally, Compton’s (2016Compton, Josh 2016 “Sorry Sorries: Image Repair After Regretted Apologies.” Public Relations Review 42: 353–358. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 357) study on regretted apologies shows that apologizers verbalize that they are “sorry for saying sorry.” He uses Benoit’s (1997Benoit, William L. 1997 “Image Repair Discourse and Crisis Communication.” Public Relations Review 23: 177–186. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, as cited in Compton, 2016Compton, Josh 2016 “Sorry Sorries: Image Repair After Regretted Apologies.” Public Relations Review 42: 353–358. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 354) five primary image repair strategies in analyzing the regretted apologies of politicians and celebrities: (1) denial, (2) evasion of responsibility, (3) reduction of offensiveness, (4) corrective action, (5) and mortification. This research is important because it discusses a different type of an apology, but Compton (2016)Compton, Josh 2016 “Sorry Sorries: Image Repair After Regretted Apologies.” Public Relations Review 42: 353–358. DOI logoGoogle Scholar cautions against its constant use because some of the strategies might become less effective when repeated.

Given these previous explorations, the current study situates itself in this niche, guided by the aforementioned assertions and by applying Bekalu’s (2006)Bekalu, Mesfin A. 2006 “Presupposition in News Discourse.” Discourse & Society 17: 147–172. DOI logoGoogle Scholar framework in analyzing apologies, albeit with some modifications. In his study, Bekalu (2006)Bekalu, Mesfin A. 2006 “Presupposition in News Discourse.” Discourse & Society 17: 147–172. DOI logoGoogle Scholar uses a combination of Van Dijk’s 2000Van Dijk, Teun A. 2000 “Cognitive Discourse Analysis.” March 10 2021 http://​www​.discursos​.org​/unpublished%20articles​/cogn​-dis​-anal​.htm and 2004 2004 “Knowledge and News.” Revista Canaria de Estudios Ingleses 49:71–86. works on the typology of knowledge and presuppositions and Sperber and Wilson’s (1986Sperber, Dan, and Deirde Wilson 1986Relevance: Communication & Cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar, 1995 1995Relevance: Communication & Cognition. 2nd ed. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar) Relevance Theory to analyze his data. This present study takes only Van Dijk’s typology of knowledge focusing on Scope.

Scope has been chosen as the focal category because it deals with the extent to which information is shared, thereby being directly related to what a participant presupposes another participant to know. It has six subtypes: Personal, Interpersonal, Group, Institutional, National, and Cultural (Bekalu 2006Bekalu, Mesfin A. 2006 “Presupposition in News Discourse.” Discourse & Society 17: 147–172. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 151). These six typologies are used in our present study to answer the first research question regarding which knowledge types can be found in the selected apologies.

As for presuppositions, this study uses Bekalu’s (2006)Bekalu, Mesfin A. 2006 “Presupposition in News Discourse.” Discourse & Society 17: 147–172. DOI logoGoogle Scholar definition that refers to the listener’s background knowledge, which the speaker believes the former possesses and does not need to be reiterated. These are discourse presuppositions which are taken-for-granted concepts that go unsaid to help communication become more efficient. Bekalu (2006Bekalu, Mesfin A. 2006 “Presupposition in News Discourse.” Discourse & Society 17: 147–172. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 150) has chosen to concentrate on discourse presuppositions, and this study’s assertions do too.

3.Methods

3.1Data source and data gathering

Sixteen (16) public apologies comprised the data source of this study. These apologies were chosen based on their availability online and the popularity of the incidents prompting each of these apologies. In this case, top Google results were selected because those reflect not only recent incidents, but also those that have been most discussed by the public. The apologies were taken from public websites, such as news outlets and human-interest websites, as well as social media sites, such as Facebook and Twitter.

To delimit the study, we only selected the apologies that were written in English and made by public figures towards Filipino citizens (public or private). A public figure is defined in this study as a person or an entity (e.g. a business leader/company, a social media personality, a politician, a celebrity) that has an influential position in the society or “has participated in a particular public controversy” (Merriam-Webster Dictionary, 2021Merriam-Webster (2021) S.v. “Public Figure.” https://​www​.merriam​/webster​.com​/dictionary​/public%20figure).

3.2Data analysis

To further narrow the scope of the study to the linguistic aspect of apologies, only the written manuscripts were analyzed. No paralinguistic elements (such as gestures and/or voice tone) were included. The apologies were then divided into T-Units (one sentence is equal to one T-Unit) to easily categorize the information. All together the sixteen (16) apologies contained 149 sentences; hence, there were a total of 149 T-Units analyzed. These T-Units were further segmented into a categorized table for easier analysis. The table included the following information: Apology Number, Apology Name (based on the apologizer’s name), T-Unit Number, T-Unit, Knowledge Type, and Presupposition.

During this coding stage, each T-Unit was tagged with one or more knowledge types (i.e., Personal, Interpersonal, Group, Institutional, National and Cultural). Bekalu’s (2006)Bekalu, Mesfin A. 2006 “Presupposition in News Discourse.” Discourse & Society 17: 147–172. DOI logoGoogle Scholar definitions of the knowledge types were applied in this study. Personal knowledge is knowledge that only the apologizer has; Interpersonal knowledge is knowledge that the apologizer shares with people directly or indirectly involved in the apology, such as his or her family and the apologizee; Group is when the apologizer either invokes (inclusive) or shares (exclusive) the knowledge to or with a particular set of people (e.g. fans, supporters); Institutional is similar to Group in that it can also be inclusive or exclusive, but the range of the set is more delineated (e.g. school, church, organization); National, on the other hand, invokes the knowledge of a country; and finally, Cultural is knowledge that goes beyond geographic borders and can be shared by multiple nationalities.

Afterwards, frequency counting was performed to answer the first research question and report on the patterns identified in the qualitative analysis. As for the second research question, it was answered by extracting presuppositions from each T-Unit, with a single T-Unit containing one or more presuppositions. Specifically, the analysis focused on the propositional content of apology, which is the Act done by the speaker that merits his/her apology. The analysis proceeded to answer the question: “What type of information is usually left unsaid regarding the Act done and future actions to be done to atone for the Act (guilt)?” Assertions were also made as to why this information was left unsaid and what the consequences were for leaving them implicit. The next section summarizes the results of the tabulation and analysis.

4.Results and analysis

The frequency count for the first research question regarding knowledge types (Table 1) shows that the most prevalent knowledge type is Personal with 37.34%, closely followed by Group with 24.68%. On the other hand, Cultural knowledge type is the least used type in the data with only three (3) occurrences, making up 1.86%.

Table 1.Knowledge types in apologies
Knowledge type Frequency (N = 158) Percentage (N = 158)
Personal  59     37.34%
Interpersonal  20     12.66%
Group  39     24.68%
Institutional  33     20.89%
National   4      2.53%
Cultural   3     1.9%
Total 158* 100%

Here are excerpts that exemplify the knowledge types:

(1)
Personal:

Apology [1]; T-Unit [2]

Speaker:

Christopher Ad Castillo (a director)

Offense:

Threatening online messages

Target Addressee:

Petersen Vargas (a director)

“You work hard on a film and that becomes personal and I understand that not everyone will like it.”

In the selected public apologies, there is a considerable amount of information that only the apologizer is aware of, which includes, but is not limited to, personal feelings and intentions. The prevalence of this type of knowledge may be due to its nature. Since the knowledge is personal, it necessitates being made public for the apologizer to have his/her side be known and understood, with the hopes of seeming more sympathetic to the receivers.

In this example, the knowledge type is considered personal because the speaker is the director of the film involved in the apology and his perspective of working on the film and feelings towards the reception of the film are exclusive to him. In T-Unit [2], he shares his knowledge of how difficult it had been to work on it and expounds on his belief that people will have varied opinions towards his work.

(2)
Group:

Apology [5]; T-Unit [49]

Speaker:

Regina Ip (a politician)

Offense:

Accused of racist and sexist remarks in her article

Target Addressee:

Filipino maids in Hong Kong

“Unfortunately, the way my article was misinterpreted in some quarters has led many to believe that I was sexist or racist and was pointing a finger at the Filipino maids.”

As for the Group knowledge type, the 24.68% consists of information that a number of people know because they are either directly or indirectly involved in the apology. In the corpus, these involved parties include apologizees, families and relatives of apologizees, colleagues, supporters, witnesses, and organizations. In the apologies analyzed, this type of knowledge is used in two ways: first, to highlight that the apologizer has beliefs similar to other people, thereby minimizing the gravity of the error; or second, to acknowledge that the apologizer has beliefs different from others, thus prompting the apology.

In this example, the knowledge type is considered a Group Knowledge type because it directly involves a number of people: the politician apologizing for her remarks in an article and the people who read the article and branded the politician “racist” or “sexist.” Some of these readers included the Filipino maids who were allegedly critiqued in her article. The speaker here is using the Group Knowledge type in the second way, and that is to indicate the difference in beliefs between her and others with regard to how offensive her remarks were intended to be.

(3)
Interpersonal:

Apology [2]; T-Unit [11]

Speaker:

Melissa Mendez (an actress)

Offense:

Bodily harm

Target Addressee:

Rey Pamaran (a businessman)

“This incident has caused a lot of pain and trouble to me and my family, as well as the other party involved.”

The Interpersonal knowledge type, which accounts for 12.66%, is similar to the Group knowledge type, albeit it only involves those directly affected by the apology. The use of interpersonal knowledge is expected because for the apology to even exist, apologizers and apologizees are meant to share the same information. If an apologizee or a third-party witness does not react in a way that makes it necessary for the apologizer to perform an apology, then the apology will not be produced. Another use for the interpersonal knowledge type is to garner support for the apologizer. He or she can invoke the shared feelings of those involved to temper the reactions of the apology receivers.

In Apology [2], T-Unit [11], the Interpersonal Knowledge Type is invoked because the speaker/apologizer specifies the negative effects (pain and trouble) shared by the speaker, the speaker’s family, the addressee, and the addressee’s family, all of whom are directly affected by the incident and the apology stemming from the incident. It differs from the Group Knowledge

Type because other witnesses or readers of the apology do not share the same information.

(4)
Institutional:

Apology [13]; T-Unit [108]

Speaker:

BAYO (A Filipino-owned clothing company in the Philippines)

Offense:

A mixed-race ad campaign that was viewed as racist/discriminatory towards Filipinos

Target Addressee:

“[T]hose who have been offended or felt discriminated against”

“Our company and our partners have always taken pride in being pro-Filipino as we continue to celebrate our uniqueness and achievements.”

(5)
National:

Apology [7]; T-Unit [75]

Speaker:

Miss Universe Germany Sarah-Lorraine

Offense:

Verbal criticism, saying that Miss Colombia should have won Miss Universe

Target Addressee:

Miss Universe Philippines Pia Wurtzbach

“Congrats to our friends of Philippines for winning the crown after all.”

(6)
Cultural:

Apology [12]; T-Unit [101]

Speaker:

Alec Baldwin (an actor)

Offense:

Comment on getting a mail-order bride from the Philippines

Target Addressee:

“Anyone who took offense”

“Such anger and frustration about the issue of sex trafficking is understandable.”

The same logic operates in the occurrence of the Institutional, National, and Cultural knowledge types. They occur less frequently in the data (with the Cultural knowledge type occurring the least at 1.9%) because most of the selected apologies, although public, are directed to limited recipients, with the rest acting merely as an audience to the “social drama” (Kampf, 2013 2013 “The Discourse of Public Apologies: Modes of Realization, Interpretation and Mediation.” In Public Apology Between Ritual and Regret, ed. by Daniël Cuypers, Daniel Janssen, Jacques Haers, and Barbara Segaert, 145–165. Netherlands: Rodopi. DOI logoGoogle Scholar).

For the Institutional Knowledge Type, T-Unit [108] is an example because it discusses the value of pride that is supposedly held by specific institutions. In this case, these institutions are the company issuing the apology (Bayo) and its shareholders/partners. Their involvement is highlighted by the verbiage “[o]ur company and our partners” and the mention of actions taken to promote a certain ideal (i.e., “we continue to celebrate our uniqueness and achievements”).

On the other hand, an apology is likely to reach National knowledge when the error being apologized for deals with highly political or diplomatic matters of a country, such as the verbal criticism of a national beauty pageant contestant (Apology [7], T-Unit [75]). This apology involves representatives of two countries (Germany and the Philippines) who are considered members of the national sphere.

Lastly, Cultural knowledge can deal with widespread social conventions, such as the avoidance of negative stereotypes against a particular group of people, which is what Apology [12] includes. In T-Unit [101], the Cultural Knowledge Type is invoked because it relies on a widely held societal belief that sex trafficking is immoral and illegal, and thus is an issue that causes “anger and frustration.” The T-Unit validates the existence of this knowledge by expressing that such emotions are “understandable.”

As regards the second research question, the following patterns emerge from the presuppositions extracted from the T-Units:

  1. Apologizers presuppose that the audience is already aware of what they are apologizing for.

  2. Apologizers presuppose that the audience is already aware of specific actions to be done after the apology.

The first pattern is based on the observation that a majority of the apologies no longer mention the transgression or what is being apologized for. In addition, wrongs are glossed over by other words such as “shortcoming,” “misunderstanding,” and vague terms such as “event,” “what I did” or “what happened.” This finding supplements Kampf’s (2009)Kampf, Zohar 2009 “Public (non-)apologies: The Discourse of Minimizing Responsibility.” Journal of Pragmatics 41: 2257–2270. DOI logoGoogle Scholar generic names for offenses (i.e., incident, hurt/harm/damage, words, mistake, about that).

The interesting finding on the linguistic choices of apologizers to omit or only vaguely refer to their offenses is exemplified in the following excerpts:

(7)

Apology [4]; T-Unit [28]

“I do want to apologize for what happened the other night.”

This excerpt is from an apology by American boxer, Floyd Mayweather Jr., who was accused of making racist remarks against Manny Pacquiao, a Filipino boxer. Although the direct speech act of apology via the performative verb “apologize” is present and the apologizer alludes to these remarks in the next sentences, the first sentence omits the cause of the apology through the use of the gloss “what happened,” presupposing that something did happen, leaving the recipient/s of the apology to figure out what it is. In addition, Mayweather Jr. used the generic term “everybody” to address his recipients, failing to mention Pacquiao who was the subject of his tirade.

(8)

Apology [2]; T-Unit [10]

“In light of the recent incident that involved me and Mr. Rey Pamaran, I would just like to simply apologize for my untoward actions and move on from this.”

This is part of an apology given by Melissa Mendez, an actress, to a private individual, Rey Pamaran. In the excerpt, Mendez mentions the offense only as a “recent incident.” Although she includes the names of the addressee, she does not elaborate on this incident or the “untoward actions,” other than to say that she is apologetic and would like to move on.

(9)

Apology [7]; T-Unit [68]

“She is really sorry if the video suggests anything else than that.”

This line comes from the apology of Miss Universe Germany to Miss Universe Philippines (and by extension, to Filipinos). The rest of her apology touches on the controversy regarding the incorrect announcement of Miss Colombia as Miss Universe 2015; however, it does not detail which video she refers to and what exactly was said in the video that viewers may have misinterpreted. In the T-Unit before it (T-Unit [67]), Miss Germany states, “[a]s well for Pia Miss Philippines that she didn’t have her real crowning moment” to give a little context of the event that preempted the video, but again, she does not go further into the statements she is apologizing for.

(10)

Apology [16]; T-Unit [145] and [146]

“We regret the upload of the recent video on Malaysia. The video was developed locally by an agency and uploaded in error and the contents were NOT approved by Aegis Corporate.”

This is an excerpt from an apology by Aegis, a Business Process Outsourcing (BPO) company, for a Malaysian advertisement that disparaged the Philippines as an unsuitable country for business. The company mentions where the offensive statements were found, and that it was not approved for publication. However, the exact verbiage in the video is left out of the apology. The reader can only get a sense of what the offensive statements were because further in the statement, the company highlights the good experience they had in the Philippines and that it has been a “key to [their] success” (T-Unit [148]), thereby alluding that the statements in the video contained the opposite message.

The second pattern of presupposition works along the same vein as the first: there is another piece of information missing, and this time, it is what happens after the apology. Apologizers are expected to atone for their perceived sins through concrete action (Boyd, 2011Boyd, David P. 2011 “Art and Artifice in Public Apologies.” Journal of Business Ethics 104: 299–309. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). Most of the apologies in the data, however, seem to not follow this guideline. There are those that allude to future action, but not concrete, detailed plans of action. Words like “re-examination” are frequently used, as shown in Apology [14] below:

(11)

Apology [14]; T-Unit [121]

“We also assure you, our beloved people, that we shall re-examine the manner of our collaboration with government agencies for purposes of helping the poor, making sure that pastoral sensibilities are respected and the highest ethical standards are observed.”

For Example (11), an apology made by the Catholic Bishops Conference of the Philippines (CBCP) mentions a re-examination of the “manner of collaboration” with government agencies for charitable reasons, but the steps of this re-examination and what changes it entails are omitted in the apology. Another sentence (T-Unit [125]) mentions an examination of values, but once again, the process (and which values it will affect) is entirely left out. This apology was released in response to allegations that some bishops accepted luxury vehicles bought with the funds of the Philippine Charity Sweepstakes Office (PCSO). Coincidentally, any specific mention of PCSO or the vehicles is likewise omitted in the official transcript.

In Aegis’ apology (Apology 16) regarding a discriminatory video released under its name, the company does not only leave out the exact statements in question; it is also unclear about how it will handle the creation of future marketing materials. In fact, its apology only includes what the company purports to be practices already in action that should prevent the distribution of any derogatory material. This is shown in Example (12) below:

(12)

Apology [16]; T-Unit [147]: “We are a global company and strongly care about the broader communities in which we operate and are fully committed to both diversity and inclusion.”

As can be deduced from T-Unit [147], how exactly the company is committed to diversity and inclusion or more specifically, how these ideologies manifest in company policies is not stated, but this part of the apology can perhaps substitute for an act of reparation.

More commonly occurring than the allusions exemplified in Examples (11) and (12) are the complete omissions of post-apology measures. It can be deduced that the offenders believe that the apology ends once it is issued. However, when working within the paradigm of presupposition, it can also be argued that the recipients of the apologies might also assume that the most basic post-apology action will be done, and that is for the apologizers not to re-offend. Because the offenders have been called out on their behavior and have chosen to release a public apology, a valid presupposition would be that the public apology will deter them from committing the same mistake, lest they face legal repercussions or greater backlash and possible loss of good social standing or business profit. Another view is that the apologizers have intentionally omitted the mention of future actions because this is additional work on their part. The explicit enumeration of any reparative steps attaches them even more to the offense that they are trying to disassociate from. In short, the omission of further action works in two ways: first, it shifts the burden of apology work to the audience or recipients by having them extract the implications of “future action” from the apology; and second, it frees the offender from additional commitment that is more difficult to deny and, if not fulfilled, can more likely lead to even more public grievance.

5.Discussion

If there is one assertion that this paper can make with confidence and can be supported by research that has come before it (Boyd, 2011Boyd, David P. 2011 “Art and Artifice in Public Apologies.” Journal of Business Ethics 104: 299–309. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Kampf, 2009Kampf, Zohar 2009 “Public (non-)apologies: The Discourse of Minimizing Responsibility.” Journal of Pragmatics 41: 2257–2270. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Myers, 2015), it is that apologies are strategic. Consequentially, presuppositions that are formed within these apologies are equally calculated. This can be seen in the prevalent knowledge types and themes that emerge from the presuppositions extracted from the data. For example, although the Personal knowledge type is the most prevalent among all knowledge types, it only accounts for 37.34%. The rest of more than 60% of knowledge is supposedly shared by people apart from the apologizer; therefore, the information in the apologies is positioned as though the essential facts regarding the apology (what is being apologized for, who is apologizing, and who is receiving the apology) are already part of the audience’s contextual knowledge and that further elaboration is no longer necessary. Saarinen (2008Saarinen, Tania 2008 “Persuasive Presuppositions in OECD and EU Higher Education Policy Documents.” Discourse Studies 10: 341–359. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 344) rationalizes this approach by saying that presuppositions are assumptions of common ground that allow the speaker to choose which parts can be made implicit or explicit. Selecting which details will be left as presuppositions is largely based on how the speaker thinks the information will be interpreted. If the speaker decides that making the information explicit will negatively influence its reception, then he or she can present it as “common ground” to ease audience acceptance. Lewis (1979)Lewis, David 1979 “Scorekeeping in a Language Game.” Journal of Philosophical Logic 8: 339–359. DOI logoGoogle Scholar calls this “accommodation.”

The results of our present analysis show that Personal knowledge type is prevalent because apologies seem to be similar to confessions, wherein the apologizer expresses internal thoughts, feelings, and knowledge that the audience is yet to be made aware of. However, because Interpersonal, Group, Institutional, National, and Cultural knowledges are invoked, it is possible for apologizers to obscure the offense. In the case of the public apologies discussed, the apologizers’ presuppositions contain mostly two things: that both the act/offense and the restitution for the act/offense are already understood, and thereby no longer necessary to repeat. By relying on these propositional contents, the apologizers did not have to risk their reputation in the performance of the apology.

Therefore, when Boyd (2011)Boyd, David P. 2011 “Art and Artifice in Public Apologies.” Journal of Business Ethics 104: 299–309. DOI logoGoogle Scholar asks how an offender can offer an apology for an offense that is left unsaid, the analysis of this study’s data seems to provide a partial answer. Stephen (2015Stephen, Matthew D. 2015 “ ‘Can You Pass the Salt?’ The Legitimacy of International Institutions and Indirect Speech.” European Journal of International Relations 21: 768–792. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 773) calls this “plausible deniability,” a strategy used to avoid incriminating oneself because of legal implications that are associated with direct statements. By invoking knowledge types that include the audience as a knowledge source, apologizers can maintain the practice of omitting particular pieces of information and still be able to offer an apology. Moreover, Kampf (2013 2013 “The Discourse of Public Apologies: Modes of Realization, Interpretation and Mediation.” In Public Apology Between Ritual and Regret, ed. by Daniël Cuypers, Daniel Janssen, Jacques Haers, and Barbara Segaert, 145–165. Netherlands: Rodopi. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 151) states that the public context influences the reception of apologies because although it is the mode through which the apology can be delivered, it also impacts the reception and credibility of the apology. Since it is quite difficult to quantify sincerity because it depends on how the apology is received and who is receiving it, there comes a point wherein the invocation of the word “apology” may be sufficient to fulfill the social obligation. Hence, apologizers can employ different tactics that enable them to repair their reputations and, at the same time, evade legal consequences (Myers 2016Myers, Cayce 2016 “Apology, Sympathy, and Empathy: The Legal Ramifications of Admitting Fault in U.S. Public Relations Practice.” Public Relations Review 42: 176–183. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Kampf 2013 2013 “The Discourse of Public Apologies: Modes of Realization, Interpretation and Mediation.” In Public Apology Between Ritual and Regret, ed. by Daniël Cuypers, Daniel Janssen, Jacques Haers, and Barbara Segaert, 145–165. Netherlands: Rodopi. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Kampf 2009Kampf, Zohar 2009 “Public (non-)apologies: The Discourse of Minimizing Responsibility.” Journal of Pragmatics 41: 2257–2270. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). Through proper word choice, they can “determine [their] liability for the offense” (Kampf 2009Kampf, Zohar 2009 “Public (non-)apologies: The Discourse of Minimizing Responsibility.” Journal of Pragmatics 41: 2257–2270. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 2263).

Sbisà (1999)Sbisà, Marina 1999 “Ideology and the Persuasive Use of Presupposition.” In Language and Ideology: Selected Papers from the 6th International Pragmatics Conference Vol. 1, ed. by Jef Verschueren, 492–509. Antwerp: International Pragmatics Association.Google Scholar strengthens this argument by stating that presuppositions even have the power to persuade. In the case of these public apologies, presuppositions work in favor of the apologizers because the latter can still omit the more socially unacceptable parts of the apology; yet, by the mere token of calling it an “apology,” they can persuade hearers into accepting it as such, regardless of their degree of sincerity. This strategic function of presuppositions in apologies aligns with the Filipino concept of Hiya, which is commonly defined as an aversion to embarrassment (Lasquety-Reyes 2016Lasquety-Reyes, Jeremiah 2016 “In Defense of Hiya as a Filipino Virtue.” Asian Philosophy: An International Journal of the Philosophical Traditions of the East 26: 66–78. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). Because Filipinos value self-esteem, a culture of sensitivity has been built around this social value; any behavior that can put one’s self-esteem under attack is avoided at all costs (Hays 2008Hays, Jeffrey 2008 “Filipino Character and Personality: Hiya, Amor Propio, Emotions, and the Influences of Catholicism, Asia, and Spain.” March 20 2020 Http://​factsanddetails​.com​/southeast​-asia​/Philippines​/sub5​_6c​/entry​-3867​.html). Hence, indirect or evasive apologies may be a product of using presupposition as a tool to avoid self-incrimination, protect the apologizer’s self-esteem, and ensure that he or she will not feel “hiya” or deep shame that may lead to, at worst, ostracism.

6.Conclusion

This paper examines how the strategic aspects of the speech act of apology are employed by apologizers towards Filipino apologizees through their utilization of knowledge types and presupposition. The results of our analysis indicate that apologizers frequently utilize the Personal knowledge type because apologies involve personal confessions that contain thoughts and feelings that only the apologizers are aware of. Their frequent use of Interpersonal, Group, Institutional, National, and Cultural knowledges raise the possibility that these are utilized in order to obscure the apologizers’ offenses. This conclusion can be substantiated by our analyses of the apologizers’ presuppositions, which contain mostly two things: the assumption that the act/transgression has already been made known to the apologizees and the omission of the mention of restitution for the act that may hold them more accountable to their transgressions. By relying on these propositional contents, the apologizers have persuasively delivered their apologies without opening themselves up to further risks. Much like Bekalu’s (2006)Bekalu, Mesfin A. 2006 “Presupposition in News Discourse.” Discourse & Society 17: 147–172. DOI logoGoogle Scholar conclusion, these omissions have served to obscure information to meet self-serving purposes. Our present analysis supports the view that although the sincerity of apology cannot be exactly measured, its performance is a necessary feature of human interaction for image repair and management of interpersonal relationships.

Despite the restrictions imposed by our limited dataset, the findings on the strategic employment of knowledge types and the kind of presupposed information in public apologies that are discussed in this paper support previous assertions regarding the complexities of public apology. They bolster the view that although public apologies perform the act of being sorry, there are instances wherein the performance veils the possibility that the apologizers are barely or not even sorry at all. Apologizers manipulate the linguistic tools and types of knowledge available at their disposal in order to perform this ritual that fulfills multiple functions.

It is hoped that the study will prompt further inquiry into the intricacies of this social ritual, which is embedded in a cultural context where communal practices and conventions highly influence the way it is created and used. It is recommended, then, that more studies in the local setting be done using other approaches, such as corpus linguistics, cultural linguistics, and intercultural rhetoric. There can be a comparison of public apologies across cultures given the context of global communication in our time, either coming from the apologizers’ perspective or based on the recipients’ attitudes. The medium of public apologies can also be a subject of inquiry since written and oral modes have apparent differences that can most likely influence the construction and dissemination of public apologies. In connection with this, the effect of media, as shown in Kampf (2013) 2013 “The Discourse of Public Apologies: Modes of Realization, Interpretation and Mediation.” In Public Apology Between Ritual and Regret, ed. by Daniël Cuypers, Daniel Janssen, Jacques Haers, and Barbara Segaert, 145–165. Netherlands: Rodopi. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, can also be explored given the social context where some companies monopolize the dissemination of national information. Finally, it is also recommended that corpus linguistic studies be done to collect and observe the lexical realizations of apology to see if there is a pattern of usage in different cross-cultural contexts. In sum, public apologies carry with them layers of meaning-making, discourse, negotiation, and intent that can be analyzed and exhausted in a multitude of ways. In fact, the current body of data still contains uncovered linguistic realizations that researchers are welcome to revisit and reexamine in the future.

References

Ancarno, Clyde S.
2015 “When are Public Apologies ‘Successful’? Focus on British and French Apology Press Uptakes.” Journal of Pragmatics 84: 139–153. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Austin, John
1962How to Do Things with Words. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Beaver, David I.
2001Presupposition and Assertion in Dynamic Semantics. Stanford: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
Bekalu, Mesfin A.
2006 “Presupposition in News Discourse.” Discourse & Society 17: 147–172. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Benoit, William L.
1997 “Image Repair Discourse and Crisis Communication.” Public Relations Review 23: 177–186. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Bentley, Joshua M.
2015 “Shifting Identification: A Theory of Apologies and Pseudo-apologies.” Public Relations Review 41: 22–29. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Blum-Kulka, Shoshana, and Elite Olshtain
1984 “Requests and Apologies: A Cross-cultural Study of Speech Act Realization Patterns (CCSARP).” Applied Linguistics 5: 196–213. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Brown, Penelope, and Stephen Levinson
1987Politeness: Some Universals in Language Usage (Studies in Interactional Sociolinguistics 4). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Boyd, David P.
2011 “Art and Artifice in Public Apologies.” Journal of Business Ethics 104: 299–309. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Cels, Sanderijn
2015 “Interpreting Political Apologies: The Neglected Role of Performance.” Political Psychology 36: 351–360. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Coombs, Timothy, and Sherry Holladay
2008 “Comparing Apology to Equivalent Crisis Response Strategies: Clarifying Apology’s Role and Value in Crisis Communication.” Public Relations Review 34: 252–257. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Compton, Josh
2016 “Sorry Sorries: Image Repair After Regretted Apologies.” Public Relations Review 42: 353–358. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
De La Rosa, John Paul O., and Lorna B. Castro
2016 “Is It Too Late Now to Say Sorry? The Language of Public Apologies in the Contexts of American and Philippine Television.” i-manager’s Journal on English Language Teaching 6: 29–44. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Goffman, Erving
1967Interaction Ritual: Essays on Face-to-face behavior. Garden City, NY: Doubleday.Google Scholar
Gonzalez-Cruz, Maria Isabel
2012 “Apologizing in Spanish: A Study of the Strategies Used by University Students in Las Palmas De Gran Canaria.” Pragmatics 22:543–565. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Kampf, Zohar
2009 “Public (non-)apologies: The Discourse of Minimizing Responsibility.” Journal of Pragmatics 41: 2257–2270. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2013 “The Discourse of Public Apologies: Modes of Realization, Interpretation and Mediation.” In Public Apology Between Ritual and Regret, ed. by Daniël Cuypers, Daniel Janssen, Jacques Haers, and Barbara Segaert, 145–165. Netherlands: Rodopi. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Harris, Sandra, Karen Grainger, and Louise Mullany
2006 “The Pragmatics of Political Apologies.” Discourse & Society 17: 715–737. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Hays, Jeffrey
2008 “Filipino Character and Personality: Hiya, Amor Propio, Emotions, and the Influences of Catholicism, Asia, and Spain.” March 20 2020 Http://​factsanddetails​.com​/southeast​-asia​/Philippines​/sub5​_6c​/entry​-3867​.html
Huang, Yan
2007Pragmatics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hunston, Suzanne, and Thompson, Geoffrey
(eds.) 2000 Evaluation in Text: Authorial Stance and the Construction of Discourse . Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lasquety-Reyes, Jeremiah
2016 “In Defense of Hiya as a Filipino Virtue.” Asian Philosophy: An International Journal of the Philosophical Traditions of the East 26: 66–78. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Levinson, Stephen C.
1983Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David
1979 “Scorekeeping in a Language Game.” Journal of Philosophical Logic 8: 339–359. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
MacLachlan, Alice
2015 “ ‘Trust Me, I’m Sorry’: The Paradox of Public Apology.” The Monist 98 (4): 441–456. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Marrus, Michael R.
2006Official Apologies and the Quest for Historical Justice. Toronto: University of Toronto.Google Scholar
Merriam-Webster
Mojica, Leonisa
2004 “Apology Strategies Perceived to be Appropriate by Filipino-speaking Couples.” Philippine Journal of Linguistics 34: 27–40.Google Scholar
Murphy, James
2015 “Revisiting the Apology as a Speech Act: The Case of Parliamentary Apologies.” Journal of Language and Politics 14: 175–204. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Myers, Cayce
2016 “Apology, Sympathy, and Empathy: The Legal Ramifications of Admitting Fault in U.S. Public Relations Practice.” Public Relations Review 42: 176–183. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Nobles, Melissa
2008 The Politics of Official Apologies . Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Oclaret, Venjie N.
2013 “Apology Strategies of Filipino and Filipino-Chinese Third Year High School Students.” (Unpublished research paper) Philippine Normal University–Manila, Manila, Philippines.Google Scholar
Ogiermann, Eva
2009On Apologising in Negative and Positive Politeness Cultures. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Page, Ruth
2014 “Saying ‘Sorry’: Corporate Apologies Posted on Twitter.” Journal of pragmatics 62: 30–45. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Papi, Marcella B.
2003 “Implicitness.” In Handbook of Pragmatics Online, ed. by Jan-Ola Östman and Jef Verschueren, Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Saarinen, Tania
2008 “Persuasive Presuppositions in OECD and EU Higher Education Policy Documents.” Discourse Studies 10: 341–359. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Sbisà, Marina
1999 “Ideology and the Persuasive Use of Presupposition.” In Language and Ideology: Selected Papers from the 6th International Pragmatics Conference Vol. 1, ed. by Jef Verschueren, 492–509. Antwerp: International Pragmatics Association.Google Scholar
Searle, John
1979Expression and Meaning: Studies in the Theory of Speech Acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Searle, John, and Daniel Vanderveken
1985Foundations of Illocutionary Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sperber, Dan, and Deirde Wilson
1986Relevance: Communication & Cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
1995Relevance: Communication & Cognition. 2nd ed. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, Robert C.
2002 “Pragmatic Presupposition.” In Pragmatics: Critical Concepts, Vol. IV: Presupposition, Implicature and Indirect Speech Acts, ed. by Asa Kasher, 46–62. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Stephen, Matthew D.
2015 “ ‘Can You Pass the Salt?’ The Legitimacy of International Institutions and Indirect Speech.” European Journal of International Relations 21: 768–792. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Towner, Emil B.
2010 “Truly Public Apologies: Third-party Participation in Rwandan Apologetic Rhetoric.” Qualitative Research Reports in Communication 11: 63–69. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Yule, George
2006The Study of Language (3rd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Van Dijk, Teun A.
2004 “Knowledge and News.” Revista Canaria de Estudios Ingleses 49:71–86.
2005 “Contextual Knowledge Management in Discourse Production: A CDA Perspective.” In A New Agenda in (Critical) Discourse Analysis: Theory, Methodology and Interdisciplinarity, ed. by Ruth Wodak and Paul Chilton, 71–100. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Weyeneth, Robert R.
2001 “The Power of Apology and the Process of Historical Reconciliation.” The Public Historian 23 (3): 9–38. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Zhanghong, Xiu, and Yanan Li
2020 “A Pragmatic Study of Apologies Posted on Weibo by Chinese Celebrities.” International Journal of Literature and Arts 8 (2): 52–61. DOI logoGoogle Scholar

Address for correspondence

Leah Gustilo

Block 14 Lot 23 Alicante Street

Bellazona Navarre

Molino 3 Bacoor Cavite 4102

Philippines

[email protected]

Biographical notes

Jocelyn A. S. Navera has a BA and MA degree in English Studies (Major in Language) from the University of the Philippines-Diliman. She is taking her Ph.D. in Applied Linguistics at De La Salle University, Manila, where she also taught as an Assistant Professorial Lecturer. Currently, she is a participant of the 2018 Japan Exchange and Teaching (JET) Programme and is serving as one of the Assistant Language Teachers of the Okayama Prefectural Board of Education.

Leah Gustilo, Ph.D., is Associate Professor in the Department of English and Applied Linguistics, De La Salle University, Philippines. She had been involved in several research projects funded by the British Council, Fund to Assistance for Private Education (FAPE), Philippines; Japan International Cooperation Agency (JICA), Philippines; Knowledge Channel Foundation, Inc.; and University Research Coordination Office of De La Salle University. She has presented her research works in conferences in some parts of Asia, USA, and Europe.