Paralanguage and ad hoc concepts

Manuel Padilla Cruz

Abstract

Ad hoc concept construction is regarded as a case of free pragmatic enrichment, so it is presented as a non-linguistically mandated process that is automatically accomplished during mutual parallel adjustment. Recent research suggests that this lexical pragmatic process may be marked and steered by various linguistic elements. These include evaluative morphemes, lexical and phrasal items adjacent to content words, and stylistic resources like repetition or rewording. This paper argues that paralanguage may fulfil a similar enacting function and finetune the conceptual representations arising from content words on the grounds of idiosyncratic, context-dependent features or shades, as well as propositional and non-propositional information about the speaker’s psychological states. However, the paper restricts this function to expressive interjections, prosodic inputs like pitch, contrastive stress and pace or tempo, and gestural inputs such as language-like gestures, pantomimes and emblems. Conative interjections, intonation and proper gesticulation would be excluded from contributing to lexical pragmatic processes.

Keywords:
Publication history
Table of contents

1.Introduction

In an endeavour to understand how hearers arrive at the speaker’s meaning,11.Following a relevance-theoretic convention, reference to the speaker is made through the third person singular feminine pronoun, while reference to the hearer is made through the masculine pronoun. Deirdre Wilson has delved, along with Dan Sperber and colleagues, into the comprehension of content words and their contribution to communication (Sperber and Wilson 1986Sperber, Dan, and Deirdre Wilson 1986Relevance: Communication and Cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar, 1995 1995Relevance: Communication and Cognition. 2nd ed. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar; Wilson and Sperber 2002Wilson, Deirdre, and Dan Sperber 2002 “Relevance Theory.” UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 14: 249–287.Google Scholar, 2004 2004 “Relevance Theory.” In The Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. by Larry Horn, and Gregory Ward, 607–632. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar, 2012 2012Meaning and Relevance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). They regard lexical items like nouns, adjectives, verbs and adverbs as conceptual elements encoding, or activating, concepts with a denotation. However, they treat their associated concepts as not full-fledged mental objects capable of capturing what the speaker actually means. Rather, they approach them as fairly general, schematic entities requiring inferential finetuning. Made during mutual parallel adjustment, such finetuning results in particularised concepts. Due to their specificity and context-sensitiveness, these concepts are dubbed ad hoc (Sperber and Wilson 1997 1997 “The Mapping between the Mental and the Public Lexicon.” UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 9: 107–125.Google Scholar, 1998 1998 “The Mapping between the Mental and the Public Lexicon.” In Language and Thought: Interdisciplinary Themes, ed. by Peter Carruthers, and Jill Boucher, 184–200. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 2012 2012 “The Mapping between the Mental and the Public Lexicon.” In Meaning and Relevance, ed. by Deirdre Wilson, and Dan Sperber, 31–46. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Carston 2000 2000 “Explicature and Semantics.” UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 12: 1–44.Google Scholar, 2002a 2002aThoughts and Utterances. The Pragmatics of Explicit Communication. Oxford: Blackwell. DOI logoGoogle Scholar).

In relevance-theoretic pragmatics, ad hoc concept formation is presented as a case of free enrichment of a logical form (Carston 2010a 2010a “Lexical Pragmatics, Ad Hoc Concepts and Metaphor: From a Relevance Theory Perspective.” Italian Journal of Linguistics 22 (1): 153–180.Google Scholar, 2010b 2010b “Metaphor: Ad Hoc Concepts, Literal Meaning and Mental Images.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 110 (3): 295–321. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). It is described as an inferential development of the conceptual components of such a mental structure that is characterised by two features:

  1. It is necessary for obtaining a fully propositional form that may be evaluated in terms of truthfulness.

  2. It is completely exempt from mandate by any linguistic element, so it operates automatically.

Despite its automaticity, the output of this lexical pragmatic process is acknowledged to depend on other sentential material, manifest information and paralanguage.

However, the need for ad hoc concept construction may be signalled, and the output of the process may be greatly determined, by a number of linguistic elements. A first group includes morphological items like the diminutive and augmentative affixes available in some inflectional languages. A second group comprises lexical and/or phrasal elements like determiners, adjectives, expressive expletives and evidential participles. Still, stylistic resources such as lexical repetition and rewording may cause and direct the formation of ad hoc concepts. These elements and choices would work as overt signals or indicators that specific conceptual representations are needed in order to accurately grasp the speaker’s meaning. They would even signal what direction their creation should follow (Padilla Cruz 2020 2020 “Towards a Relevance-Theoretic Approach to the Diminutive Morpheme.” Russian Journal of Linguistics 24 (4): 774–795. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 2022a 2022a “Is Free Enrichment always Free? Revisiting Ad Hoc Concept Construction.” Journal of Pragmatics 187: 130–143. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 2022b 2022b “On the Interpretation of Utterances with Expressive Expletives.” Pragmatics & Cognition 28 (2): 252–276. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, in press In press. “Ad Hoc Concepts, Affective Attitude and Epistemic Stance.” Pragmatics & Cognition.). The list of elements and devices could certainly be enlarged with additional ones from certain languages, language families or even less widely-spoken varieties.

Paralanguage, which has also intrigued Wilson, could play similar enacting and assistive roles. The need and expectation for particular notional representations may be overtly signalled by: elements like interjections, which are halfway between lexical items and vocal gestures; suprasegmental or prosodic utterance features like pitch and tempo, which affect how words and/or phrases are delivered; and visual clues like gestures or facial expressions, which accompany speech. These can also assist hearers in their formation. Therefore, this paper ascertains the contribution of these elements to ad hoc concept construction. It will show that, in addition to steering the formation of specialised concepts capturing specific types, features or aspects of what the speaker refers to through content words, some paralinguistic elements may also contribute attitudinal or emotional information. This might have far-reaching theoretic implications.

Paralanguage is a rather broad and heterogeneous category. In relevance-theoretic pragmatics, its varied elements and clues have been analysed in procedural or non-translational terms: instead of encoding conceptual material, they would enact the activation or creation of a representation of the speaker’s attitude(s) towards, and psychological state(s) about, what she says (Wilson and Wharton 2006Wilson, Deirdre, and Tim Wharton 2006 “Relevance and Prosody.” Journal of Pragmatics 38 (10): 1559–1579. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Wharton 2009 2009Pragmatics and Non-Verbal Communication. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). This representation has been claimed to make up a layer that is superordinate to that occupied by the propositional representation of what the speaker says: the higher-level explicature.

If paralanguage helps specify concepts as regards the speaker’s attitude(s) towards or emotion(s) about what she denotes, information about these would not need to be solely represented as an additional mental layer. It may instead find a place among the constellation of beliefs and information stored within a conceptual entity, thus enriching it. On the other hand, the characterisation of the procedure encoded or activated by paralanguage would need revising: it should not be solely presented as triggering the construction of attitudinal or emotional descriptions.

This paper firstly gives an overview of the paralinguistic elements and features that will be object of discussion, and sorts them out into three categories. Next, it summarises the overall relevance-theoretic approach to paralanguage. Then, the paper explains the ideas about concepts adopted by Sperber and Wilson in their most seminal and influential framework, and traces their subsequent evolution as a result of the research programme undertaken by Wilson and colleagues. After doing so, the paper centres on how paralanguage may contribute to lexical pragmatic processes and examines whether all paralinguistic inputs may do so. Finally, it offers some concluding remarks.

2.Paralanguage: A brief overview

Paralanguage is sometimes considered to include only vocal characteristics of speech that are not properly part of a language, and hence to exclude facial expressions, hand gestures and bodily postures and movements. However, it is also assumed to include all the perceptible resources that help speakers transmit meaning (Wharton 2012 2012 “Pragmatics and Prosody.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. by Keith Allan, and Kasia M. Jaszczolt, 567–584. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 571). It does not only encompass audible prosodic, or suprasegmental, characteristics such as pitch, word and sentence stress, contrastive stress, intonation contours, pace or tempo, and rhythm. It also includes, on the one hand, elements halfway between proper words and vocal gestures: interjections. On the other hand, paralanguage includes an infinite variety of very subtle or patently overt non-vocal, visual clues, such as facial expressions, gestures, movements, postures or poses. Accordingly, paralanguage can be sorted out into three categories.

2.1Interjections

Interjections make up a fairly broad word class (Aijmer 2004Aijmer, Karin 2004 “Interjections in a Contrastive Perspective.” In Emotion in Dialogic Interaction: Advances in the Complex, ed. by Edda Weigand, 99–120. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; O’Connell and Kowal 2005O’Connell, Daniel C., and Sabine Kowal 2005 “Where Do Interjections Come from? A Psycholinguistic Analysis of Shaw’s Pygmalion .” Journal of Psycholinguistic Research 34 (5): 497–514. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Ameka 2006 2006 “Interjections.” In Encyclopaedia of Language and Linguistics, ed. by Keith Brown, 743–746. Amsterdam: Elsevier. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). Some of its members belong to the primary subtype because of their phonological, morphological, syntactic and semantic peculiarities, which place them halfway between vocal gestures and words; see (1). In contrast, others are transferred from other lexical categories and are hence considered secondary; see (2).

(1)

Oh! Alas! Wow! Ugh!

(2)

Shit! Hell! Fuck! Oh my God!

A further distinction is made between emotive, or expressive, interjections, which exhibit psychological states, like those above, and conative, or volitive, interjections, which evince the speaker’s desires and intentions (Wierzbicka 1991Wierzbicka, Anna 1991Cross-Cultural Pragmatics: The Semantics of Human Interaction. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 1992 1992 “The Semantics of Interjection.” Journal of Pragmatics 18 (2–3): 159–192. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Ameka 1992aAmeka, Felix K. 1992a “Interjections: The Universal yet Neglected Part of Speech.” Journal of Pragmatics 18 (2–3): 101–118. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 2006 2006 “Interjections.” In Encyclopaedia of Language and Linguistics, ed. by Keith Brown, 743–746. Amsterdam: Elsevier. DOI logoGoogle Scholar).22.Still, other interjections may be phatic (Ameka 1992b 1992b “The Meaning of Phatic and Conative Interjections.” Journal of Pragmatics 18 (2–3): 245–271. DOI logoGoogle Scholar) or refer to verbal performance, manage conversation and work as discourse markers (Clark and Fox Tree 2002Clark, Herbert H., and Jean E. Fox Tree 2002 “Using uh and um in Spontaneous Speaking.” Cognition 84 (1): 73–11. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). This is the case of (3), which is used to draw an individual’s attention, or (4), which is employed to ask for silence:

(3)

Hey!

(4)

Shush!

Interjections have often been seen as instinctive, involuntary and symptomatic signals (Rosier 2000Rosier, Laurence 2000 “Interjection, subjectivité, expressivité et discourse rapport à l’écrit: Petits effets d’un petit discourse.” Cahiers de Praxématique 34: 19–49. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Schourup 2001Schourup, Lawrence 2001 “Rethinking well .” Journal of Pragmatics 33 (7): 1025–1060. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Kleiber 2006Kleiber, Georges 2006 “Sémiotique de l’interjection.” Langages 161 (1): 10–23. DOI logoGoogle Scholar), but their production usually involves a conscious assessment of the communicative situation and a selection from among a set of candidate items (Światkowska 2006Światkowska, Marcela 2006 “L’interjection: Entre deixis et anaphore.” Langages 161 (1): 47–56. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). Some authors regard interjections as fully conceptual (Wierzbicka 1991Wierzbicka, Anna 1991Cross-Cultural Pragmatics: The Semantics of Human Interaction. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 1992 1992 “The Semantics of Interjection.” Journal of Pragmatics 18 (2–3): 159–192. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Ameka 1992aAmeka, Felix K. 1992a “Interjections: The Universal yet Neglected Part of Speech.” Journal of Pragmatics 18 (2–3): 101–118. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 1992b 1992b “The Meaning of Phatic and Conative Interjections.” Journal of Pragmatics 18 (2–3): 245–271. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 2006 2006 “Interjections.” In Encyclopaedia of Language and Linguistics, ed. by Keith Brown, 743–746. Amsterdam: Elsevier. DOI logoGoogle Scholar), while others deny this (Wharton 2001Wharton, Tim 2001 “Natural Pragmatics and Natural Codes.” UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 13: 109–161.Google Scholar, 2003 2003 “Interjection, Language and the ‘Showing/Saying’ Continuum.” Pragmatics and Cognition 11 (1): 39–91. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 2009 2009Pragmatics and Non-Verbal Communication. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). However, their specialisation and stabilisation to repeatedly communicate concrete, relatively easily identifiable feelings or emotions may associate some interjections with rather vague, fuzzy or general notions and others with more specific ones (Padilla Cruz 2009aPadilla Cruz, Manuel 2009a “Might Interjections Encode Concepts? More Questions than Answers.” Łodź Papers in Pragmatics 5 (2): 241–270.Google Scholar). If, as Dámasio (1994)Dámasio, António 1994Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason and the Human Brain. New York: Avon.Google Scholar and Goleman (1995)Goleman, Daniel 1995Emotional Intelligence. New York: Bantam Books.Google Scholar suggest, there is a set of basic emotions, such emotions could be paired to concepts, which could in turn be associated with the interjections expressing them.33.For Damásio (1994)Dámasio, António 1994Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason and the Human Brain. New York: Avon.Google Scholar, such elementary emotions are happiness, sadness, anger, fear and disgust, while Goleman (1995)Goleman, Daniel 1995Emotional Intelligence. New York: Bantam Books.Google Scholar also adds enjoyment, love, surprise and shame.

2.2Prosody

Prosody groups a wide variety of audible variations in speech production. They are usually paired with facial expressions, hand gestures and other kinetic behaviours in order to convey affective and attitudinal information, as well as information about the speaker’s physiological or psychological state(s) (McNeill 1992McNeill, David 1992Hand and Mind: What Gestures Reveal about Thought. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar; Ladd 1996Ladd, Robert 1996Intonational Phonology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar; Gussenhoven 2004Gussenhoven, Carlos 2004The Phonology of Tone and Intonation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Kendon 2004 2004Gesture: Visible Action as Utterance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). Although prosodic features have been approached as linguistic or natural, spontaneous and unintentional features (Halliday 1967Halliday, M. A. K. 1967Intonation and Grammar in British English. The Hague: Mouton. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Bolinger 1983Bolinger, Dwight 1983 “Where Does Intonation Belong?Journal of Semantics 2 (2): 101–120. DOI logoGoogle Scholar), they are considered to vary, to a greater or lesser extent, in terms of their linguistic nature, naturalness or language-specificity.

Pitch refers to the acoustic highness or lowness with which a word, phrase or whole sentence is uttered. It certainly prompts the deduction of a wide array of impressions and implicit contents, some of which have to do with affective or attitudinal overtones (Couper-Kuhlen 1986Couper-Kuhlen, Elizabeth 1986An Introduction to English Prosody. Tübingen: Niemeyer.Google Scholar; Wilson and Wharton 2006Wilson, Deirdre, and Tim Wharton 2006 “Relevance and Prosody.” Journal of Pragmatics 38 (10): 1559–1579. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Wharton 2009 2009Pragmatics and Non-Verbal Communication. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 2012 2012 “Pragmatics and Prosody.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. by Keith Allan, and Kasia M. Jaszczolt, 567–584. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). For example, a high pitch makes a no sound forceful and unquestionable, while a low one may convey overtones of kindness or condescension.

While lexical stress is the prominence given to a word syllable and can mark meaning or grammatical differences – e.g., ˈaddict (noun) vs. aˈddict (verb) – sentence stress is the alternation of prominent and non-prominent words in a sentence to indicate important information. Additionally, languages like English avail themselves of contrastive stress, which contrasts lexical items with others that have previously been mentioned in terms of meaning or some trait (Ladd 1996Ladd, Robert 1996Intonational Phonology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar; Madella 2020Madella, Pauline 2020 “Prosodic Pointing: From Pragmatic Awareness to Pragmatic Competence in Chinese Hearers of L2 English.” PhD diss. University of Brighton.):

(5)

Do you need a ˈblue pen or a ˈred pen?

Intonation is the voice movements made while speaking. Up until recently, falling and rising tones have respectively been paired with asserting and questioning, while falling-rising contours have been linked to overtones of insecurity, hesitation, doubtfulness or disappointment. In turn, rising-falling ones have been associated with feelings of surprise, pleasure, happiness or amusement, and a levelled intonation was connected with apathy, indifference, or lack of enthusiasm (Couper-Kuhlen 1986Couper-Kuhlen, Elizabeth 1986An Introduction to English Prosody. Tübingen: Niemeyer.Google Scholar; Hirschberg and Ward 1995Hirschberg, Julia, and Gregory Ward 1995 “The Interpretation of the High-Rise Question Contour in English.” Journal of Pragmatics 24 (4): 407–412. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). Yet, on many occasions exact meanings and overtones can neither be precisely attributed to tones nor be said to encode them. Finally, pace is the speed or rate of delivery of spoken speech, whereas rhythm is the movement achieved while speaking as a result of timing, lexical stress and syllable length.

2.3Kinesics

Kinesics is a broad category that includes hand, arm and body movements – gestuality – and facial expressions. Not all of them have the same characteristics, are used in the same fashion and communicate in the same manner. Concerning gestuality, Kendon (1988)Kendon, Adam 1988 “How Gestures Can Become like Words?” In Cross-Cultural Perspectives in Nonverbal Communication, ed. by Fernando Poyatos, 131–141. Toronto: Hogrefe.Google Scholar and McNeill (1992)McNeill, David 1992Hand and Mind: What Gestures Reveal about Thought. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar differentiate between various types:

  1. Proper gesticulation, which is absolutely spontaneous hand and arm movements and touches accompanying speech: scratching, twirling hair, fidgeting, picking objects, etc. They reveal a variety of states like uneasiness, arousal or anxiety.

  2. Language-like gestures, which are integrated into a linguistic string and contribute to its interpretation: the hand and finger movements that point to objects, highlight words, mark rhythm, or even illustrate the content of the message, like the hand movements to indicate the shape, size or largeness of objects.

  3. Pantomimes, which are movements appearing in isolation and depicting objects or actions, as if they were icons: the movements to mime opening a bottle, drinking a cup of tea or skiing.

  4. Emblems, which are culture-specific gestures conveying agreed-upon meanings: hitchhikers’ raised thumb or the ‘ok’ sign with index and thumb shaping a circle.

  5. Sign languages, which are proper rule-governed linguistic systems.

From the first to the last type, gestures become less natural and spontaneous, depend less on the presence of language itself and become more linguistic. Therefore, gestures may involuntarily and/or accidentally unveil affective attitudes and psychological states, or decidedly, perhaps exaggeratedly, display them (Wharton 2009 2009Pragmatics and Non-Verbal Communication. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 2012 2012 “Pragmatics and Prosody.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. by Keith Allan, and Kasia M. Jaszczolt, 567–584. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar).

3.Paralanguage in relevance-theoretic pragmatics

The enormous variety of behaviours comprised by paralanguage is often produced in an uncontrolled, unconscious manner, thus inadvertently displaying, or accidentally unveiling, some information regarding the physical or psychological state of the speaker. Although she may not have a communicative intention when producing them, these behaviours may nevertheless lead the audience to draw some conclusions. In this case, paralinguistic behaviours constitute natural signs and, as such, “are not inherently communicative” (Wharton 2012 2012 “Pragmatics and Prosody.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. by Keith Allan, and Kasia M. Jaszczolt, 567–584. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 572, emphasis in the original; see also Wharton 2009 2009Pragmatics and Non-Verbal Communication. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 114–115).

However, paralinguistic behaviours can also be produced consciously and intentionally, thus communicating some meaning naturally. They then become signals with a communicative function enabling them to convey natural meaning (meaning n ). Thus, they differ from coded verbal elements conventionally and arbitrarily conveying non-natural meaning (meaning nn ; Wharton 2003 2003 “Interjection, Language and the ‘Showing/Saying’ Continuum.” Pragmatics and Cognition 11 (1): 39–91. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 2009 2009Pragmatics and Non-Verbal Communication. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 2012 2012 “Pragmatics and Prosody.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. by Keith Allan, and Kasia M. Jaszczolt, 567–584. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar).

The cut-off point between behaviours showing meaning and linguistic elements encoding it is not clear-cut, though. There seems to be a continuum, at one extreme of which fall pure cases of showing, while standard cases of linguistic encoding fall at the other. In between would lie a wide array of cases in which more or less direct and indirect evidences of meaning combine to various degrees. Indeed, many natural signals stabilise in languages, varieties or sociocultural groups as means to constantly exhibit the same sort of meaning. Hence, they involve some encoding and trigger particular representations of the speaker’s psychological states (Wharton 2003 2003 “Interjection, Language and the ‘Showing/Saying’ Continuum.” Pragmatics and Cognition 11 (1): 39–91. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 2009 2009Pragmatics and Non-Verbal Communication. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 2012 2012 “Pragmatics and Prosody.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. by Keith Allan, and Kasia M. Jaszczolt, 567–584. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Wilson and Wharton 2006Wilson, Deirdre, and Tim Wharton 2006 “Relevance and Prosody.” Journal of Pragmatics 38 (10): 1559–1579. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). Ultimately, they may even become culture-specific emblems. Such signals would become linguistic and be governed by “a linguistic code with its own special-purpose principles or mechanisms” (Wharton 2012 2012 “Pragmatics and Prosody.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. by Keith Allan, and Kasia M. Jaszczolt, 567–584. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 574, emphasis in the original).

If utterances are already semantically underdeterminate and inference is always needed in order to arrive at the speaker’s informative intention, the underdeterminacy of purposefully used paralinguistic signals may even be greater.44.Fully determinate meaning would require words to attain absolute explicitness of speaker-intended meaning (Sperber and Wilson 2015 2015 “Beyond Speaker’s Meaning.” Croatian Journal of Philosophy 15 (44): 117–149.Google Scholar, 135–136). The information that they convey certainly resembles that communicated by linguistic elements like the attitudinal adverbials happily or sadly (Ifantidou 1992Ifantidou, Elly 1992 “Sentential Adverbs and Relevance.” UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 4: 193–214.Google Scholar), which could obviously be employed in order to communicate it more explicitly. In relevance-theoretic pragmatics, these adverbials are considered to contribute to higher-level explicatures as in (6b), or the speech-act or propositional-attitude descriptions under which the pragmatically enriched form consisting of conceptual representations is embedded:

(6)
  1. Happily, Mary has finished her thesis.

  2. [The speaker is happy/exultant that [Mary has finished her thesis]].

Relevance theorists consider that intentional meaning-showing paralinguistic behaviours also contribute to such explicatures. These behaviours convey non-translational meaning and help hearers activate specific mental attitude- or emotion-related representations or adjust their expectations of relevance (Wharton 2009 2009Pragmatics and Non-Verbal Communication. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 61–65). Just as procedural elements encode processing instructions, paralanguage encodes some content, though sometimes altogether indeterminate or ineffable, and points the hearer to a particular direction when processing the behaviours that it groups. This suggests that these context-dependent behaviours do not contribute to the truth-conditional content of utterances.

Regarding interjections, if they are appended to an utterance in initial or final position, or interrupt it, and make up a distinct tone-unit, they would be “indicators of higher-level explicatures” (Wharton 2003 2003 “Interjection, Language and the ‘Showing/Saying’ Continuum.” Pragmatics and Cognition 11 (1): 39–91. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 54). They enact attitudinal representations regarding the state of affairs that is alluded to in the proposition expressed:

(7)
  1. Alas, Mary has won the lottery!

  2. [The speaker is sad/disappointed that [Mary has won the lottery]].

When interjections occur alone, as an individual utterance, such representations concern some manifest phenomenon in a cognitive environment:55.Expressed attitudes, feelings and emotions have physiological reflexes that enable them to be experienced, and therefore characterised, with a certain intensity, vividness or temporal duration. They also have psychological correlates and may be mentally represented. But they originate as responses to phenomena or states of affairs (Damásio 1994Dámasio, António 1994Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason and the Human Brain. New York: Avon.Google Scholar). The non-translational content of interjections could also amount to procedures facilitating identification of the cause(s) of those reactions. To put it differently, the procedures that interjections would pack could signal the phenomenon or state of affairs that makes the speaker feel, or undergo, the state that she verbalises by means of an interjection (Padilla Cruz 2009b 2009b “Towards an Alternative Relevance-Theoretic Approach to Interjections.” International Review of Pragmatics 1 (1): 182–206. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). Like indexicals (Wilkins 1992Wilkins, David P. 1992 “Interjections and Deictics.” Journal of Pragmatics 18 (2–3): 119–158. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 1995 1995 “Expanding the Traditional Category of Deictic Elements: Interjections as Deictics.” In Deixis in Narrative: A Cognitive Science Perspective, ed. by Judith F. Duchan, Gail A. Bruder, and Lynne E. Hewitt, 359–386. Hillsdale: LEA.Google Scholar), interjections would thus point to the origin of, or reason for, a felt and voiced psychological state, of which they would somehow be a symptom (Rosier 2000Rosier, Laurence 2000 “Interjection, subjectivité, expressivité et discourse rapport à l’écrit: Petits effets d’un petit discourse.” Cahiers de Praxématique 34: 19–49. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Schourup 2001Schourup, Lawrence 2001 “Rethinking well .” Journal of Pragmatics 33 (7): 1025–1060. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Kleiber 2006Kleiber, Georges 2006 “Sémiotique de l’interjection.” Langages 161 (1): 10–23. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). However, to Wilkins (1992Wilkins, David P. 1992 “Interjections and Deictics.” Journal of Pragmatics 18 (2–3): 119–158. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 1995 1995 “Expanding the Traditional Category of Deictic Elements: Interjections as Deictics.” In Deixis in Narrative: A Cognitive Science Perspective, ed. by Judith F. Duchan, Gail A. Bruder, and Lynne E. Hewitt, 359–386. Hillsdale: LEA.Google Scholar), the indexical nature of interjections would make them subcategorise hidden or covert referential slots in an underlying proposition, which must be filled with extralinguistic information. This claim is not consistent with some relevance-theoretic postulates on mutual parallel adjustment and free enrichment (Carston 2000 2000 “Explicature and Semantics.” UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 12: 1–44.Google Scholar).

(8)
  1. (Upon seeing the hearer’s new outfit) Wow!

  2. [The speaker is surprised by my new outfit].

Concerning prosody, relevance theorists initially analysed it as a facilitator of syntactic segmentation, parsing and context selection (House 1989House, Jill 1989 “The Relevance of Intonation?UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 1: 3–17.Google Scholar, 1990 1990 “Intonation Structures and Pragmatic Interpretation.” In Studies in the Pronunciation of English: A Commemorative Volume in Honour of A. C. Gimson, ed. by Susan Ramsaran, 38–57. London: Routledge.Google Scholar). Pitch and intonation contours were argued to guide the retrieval of syntactic and semantic information, as well as the action that a speaker attempts to perform verbally (Clark and Lindsey 1990Clark, Billy, and Geoff Lindsey 1990 “Intonation, Grammar and Utterance Interpretation: Evidence from English Exclamatory-Inversions.” UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 2: 32–51.Google Scholar; Escandell-Vidal 1998Escandell-Vidal, Victoria 1998 “Intonation and Procedural Encoding: The Case of Spanish Interrogatives.” In Current Issues in Relevance Theory, ed. by Villy Rouchota, and Andreas H. Jucker, 169–203. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Fretheim 1998Fretheim, Thorstein 1998 “Intonation and the Procedural Encoding of Attributed Thoughts: The Case of Norwegian Interrogatives.” In Current Issues in Relevance Theory, ed. by Villy Rouchota, and Andreas H. Jucker, 205–236. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Imai 1998Imai, Kunihiko 1998 “Intonation and Relevance.” In Relevance Theory: Applications and Implications, ed. by Robyn Carston and Seiji Uchida, 69–86. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). Prosodic inputs were also thought to create impressions and alter the salience of interpretations. However, pitch and intonation have subsequently been considered to encode procedures resulting in actional and attitudinal descriptions (Wilson and Wharton 2006Wilson, Deirdre, and Tim Wharton 2006 “Relevance and Prosody.” Journal of Pragmatics 38 (10): 1559–1579. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Wharton 2009 2009Pragmatics and Non-Verbal Communication. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar):

(9)
  1. Mike, /are you joining us tonight?

  2. [The speaker asks/wants to know whether [the hearer is joining them tonight]].

(10)
  1. Another ciga˅rette?!

  2. [The speaker is angry that [the hearer is having another cigarette]].

Paralinguistic signals must be interpreted analogically, on the basis of possibly subtle changes in their features that are proportional to the psychological state causing them (Wharton 2009 2009Pragmatics and Non-Verbal Communication. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 122). But their contribution may be fairly indeterminate and their interpretation may require a greater amount of inferential labour. Due to such indeterminacy, paralinguistic signals can be situated along an explicitness–implicitness continuum depending on the amount of inferential work that their interpretation requires (Sperber and Wilson 2015 2015 “Beyond Speaker’s Meaning.” Croatian Journal of Philosophy 15 (44): 117–149.Google Scholar, 123–124). Some deliberate paralinguistic signals could quite determinately show intended meaning, even though it cannot be fully grasped or precisely paraphrased in propositional terms. In contrast, the meaning of unintentional or uncontrolled paralinguistic signals would be far more indeterminate and perhaps almost unparaphrasable.

Imagine a guest at a party said (11) with overtly evident low pitch and falling intonation upon seeing that the host is offering some cheese:

(11)

Cheese.

If the guest was known to adore cheese, (11) could easily and straightforwardly lead the hearer to construct the higher-level explicature in (12a). In this case, the meaning of low pitch and falling intonation would have been shown in a fairly determinate manner. However, by uttering (11), the guest could also intend to suggest that she is upset or angry that the guest is offering cheese, given that she does not like it or has an allergy to dairy products. If that information was unknown to a hearer, he might fail to create the attitudinal description in (12b), and the low pitch and falling intonation would also have failed to clearly and unambiguously show the guest’s attitude.

(12)
  1. [The guest is delighted that the host is serving cheese].

  2. [The guest is disappointed/angry that the host is serving cheese].

In addition to the role played by inference in determining the communicative contribution of paralinguistic elements, the interpretation of some of them crucially depends on some “specialised, perhaps dedicated, neural machinery” (Wharton 2009 2009Pragmatics and Non-Verbal Communication. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 132) – perhaps some sort of emotion-reading mental mechanism integrated in the broader mindreading mechanism (Wilson 2012 2012 “Modality and the Conceptual–Procedural Distinction.” In Relevance Theory: More than Understanding, ed. by Ewa Wałaszewska, and Agnieszka Piskorska, 23–43. Newcastle: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.Google Scholar) – which would rely on “innately determined codes” (Wharton 2012 2012 “Pragmatics and Prosody.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. by Keith Allan, and Kasia M. Jaszczolt, 567–584. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 573).66.As supportive evidence, Wharton (2012 2012 “Pragmatics and Prosody.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. by Keith Allan, and Kasia M. Jaszczolt, 567–584. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 573) mentions that primates and humans possess a neural machinery enabling facial recognition and processing of facial expressions. However, the import of intentionally used paralanguage does not need to be a propositional representation or a small set of propositions, but may be a wide array of propositions. Furthermore, it may not be solely restricted to propositional representations, but may include, or amount to, sensorimotor representations like “images, feelings and states of mind” (Wilson and Carston 2019 2019 “Pragmatics and the Challenge of ‘Non-Propositional’ Effects.” Journal of Pragmatics 145: 31–38. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 36). These make up a special type of cognitive benefits: non-propositional effects. These are open-ended by-products of processing, which involve the activation of perceptual, emotional or sensorimotor mechanisms. They cannot be finitely paraphrased by means of a sole proposition capturing all their nuances, and different individuals may come up with distinct paraphrases (Wilson and Carston 2019 2019 “Pragmatics and the Challenge of ‘Non-Propositional’ Effects.” Journal of Pragmatics 145: 31–38. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 32). Accordingly, interjections could also trigger some sort of mental image of the speaker as she experiences some psychological state, or even emotions similar to those the speaker is thought to experience (Wilson and Wharton 2006Wilson, Deirdre, and Tim Wharton 2006 “Relevance and Prosody.” Journal of Pragmatics 38 (10): 1559–1579. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Wharton 2009 2009Pragmatics and Non-Verbal Communication. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). Likewise, specific tones and pitch may also prompt hearers to entertain diverse thoughts and experience a cascade of feelings and sensations that “cannot be pinned down to one specific proposition or small set of propositions” (Wharton 2012 2012 “Pragmatics and Prosody.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. by Keith Allan, and Kasia M. Jaszczolt, 567–584. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 580).

Summing up, paralanguage merely shows somewhat direct perceptual evidence of intended import in some cases; in others, due to its stabilisation and its being somehow coded, it shows evidence, not of that very import, but of the intention to convey it (Wilson and Carston 2019 2019 “Pragmatics and the Challenge of ‘Non-Propositional’ Effects.” Journal of Pragmatics 145: 31–38. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 34). When paralanguage is deliberately used, that evidence amounts to a pointing in the direction in which speaker-intended import is to be achieved. In other words, intentional paralanguage signals the type of content of purported effect(s), regardless of the actual nature or format of these – i.e., fully propositional or non-propositional – and of whether such effects contribute to a propositional-attitude description or to components of a representation of the proposition expressed, namely concepts. Drawing on Madella (2020)Madella, Pauline 2020 “Prosodic Pointing: From Pragmatic Awareness to Pragmatic Competence in Chinese Hearers of L2 English.” PhD diss. University of Brighton., deliberately-used paralanguage could hence be described as an ostensive pointing mechanism assisting hearers.

4.Concepts and ad hoc concepts

In Relevance: Communication and Cognition, Sperber and Wilson (1986Sperber, Dan, and Deirdre Wilson 1986Relevance: Communication and Cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar, 1995 1995Relevance: Communication and Cognition. 2nd ed. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar) endorsed the Fodorian approach to concepts (Fodor 1983Fodor, Jerry A. 1983The Modularity of Mind. Cambridge: MIT Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar), according to which a concept is an element of the language of thought that denotes something in the external world. It is linked to information that is organised into three compartments:

  1. The logical entry, which lists information about the quintessential properties of what the concept refers to.

  2. The lexical entry, which contains information about the natural-language word verbalising the concept and its pronunciation.

  3. The encyclopaedic entry, which gathers varied personal information about what the concept alludes to.

To Sperber and Wilson (1997 1997 “The Mapping between the Mental and the Public Lexicon.” UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 9: 107–125.Google Scholar, 1998 1998 “The Mapping between the Mental and the Public Lexicon.” In Language and Thought: Interdisciplinary Themes, ed. by Peter Carruthers, and Jill Boucher, 184–200. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 2012 2012 “The Mapping between the Mental and the Public Lexicon.” In Meaning and Relevance, ed. by Deirdre Wilson, and Dan Sperber, 31–46. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar), the concept–word mapping is imperfect. Although many concepts are expressible through just one natural-language word, others can be expressed through distinct terms, need a phrase in order to be expressed or completely lack a natural-language counterpart due to their specificity or complexity. Following the ground-breaking work by Barsalou (1983Barsalou, Lawrence W. 1983 “Ad Hoc Categories.” Memory & Cognition 11: 211–227. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 1987 1987 “The Instability of Graded Structure in Concepts.” In Concepts and Conceptual Development: Ecological and Intellectual Factors in Categorization, ed. by Ulric Neisser, 101–140. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar), the authors posited that the informational material associated with mental concepts is not static or unalterable, but flexible or malleable, depending on the context and the intentions attributed to the speaker. The actual denotation of words is contingent on the speaker’s informative intention, so the concepts associated with them can capture many particular speaker-intended meaning aspects or shades: “speakers, trading on their hearers’ pragmatic capacities, may employ a word to communicate any of a wide range of concepts inferable in context from the encoded lexical concept” (Carston 2012 2012 “Metaphor and the Literal/Nonliteral Distinction.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. by Keith Allan, and Kasia M. Jaszczolt, 469–492. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 491).

Wilson and colleagues, most notably Carston, surmised that concepts’ logical and encyclopaedic entries are amenable to changes: addition of new information and rearrangement or deletion of existing information (Carston 1996Carston, Robyn 1996 “Enrichment and Loosening: Complementary Processes in Deriving the Proposition Expressed.” UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 8: 61–88.Google Scholar, 2000 2000 “Explicature and Semantics.” UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 12: 1–44.Google Scholar, 2002a 2002aThoughts and Utterances. The Pragmatics of Explicit Communication. Oxford: Blackwell. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 2010a 2010a “Lexical Pragmatics, Ad Hoc Concepts and Metaphor: From a Relevance Theory Perspective.” Italian Journal of Linguistics 22 (1): 153–180.Google Scholar, 2012 2012 “Metaphor and the Literal/Nonliteral Distinction.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. by Keith Allan, and Kasia M. Jaszczolt, 469–492. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Wilson and Carston 2006Wilson, Deirdre, and Robyn Carston 2006 “Metaphor, Relevance and the ‘Emergent Property’ Issue.” Mind & Language 21 (3): 404–433. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 2007 2007 “A Unitary Approach to Lexical Pragmatics: Relevance, Inference and Ad Hoc Concepts.” In Pragmatics, ed. by Noel Burton-Roberts, 230–259. Basingstoke: Palgrave. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Wilson 2011aWilson, Deirdre 2011a “The Conceptual–Procedural Distinction: Past, Present and Future.” In Procedural Meaning: Problems and Perspectives, ed. by Victoria Escandell-Vidal, Manuel Leonetti, and Aoife Ahern, 3–31. Bingley: Emerald Group Publishing. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Hall 2017Hall, Alison 2017 “Lexical Pragmatics, Explicature and Ad Hoc Concepts.” In Semantics and Pragmatics: Drawing a Line, ed. by Ilse Depraetere, and Raphael Salkie, 55–100. Cham: Springer. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). Addition and rearrangement refine or narrow down the conceptual denotation to a more specific notional space. Thus, the context-independent concept smoke 77.Following another relevance-theoretic convention, concepts are notated in small caps. activated by (13) below may allude to a particular tobacco product (cigarettes, cigars or a pipe), a specific tobacco type (Virginia, cavendish, perique, latakia, etc.) or any other characteristic of the action that is contextually manifest, such as its intensity or frequency. This results from the addition of the corresponding information to the concept’s encyclopaedic entry or from its elevation, albeit temporarily, to a definitional status by rendering an encyclopaedic property logical.

(13)

Paul smokes.

In turn, deletion of information enables a concept to refer to something less specific than its lexically-encoded sense. Thus, oval in (14) below could refer to an oval-like shape as a consequence of the erasure of the requirement of perfect and absolute ovality from its logical entry.

(14)

The town’s plaza is oval.

These modifications in conceptual entries match two processes affecting concepts: narrowing, or strengthening, and broadening, or loosening. They are characterised as automatic because they always operate regardless of the occurrence of other input elements (Carston 2000 2000 “Explicature and Semantics.” UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 12: 1–44.Google Scholar; Jary 2016Jary, Mark 2016 “Rethinking Explicit Utterance Content.” Journal of Pragmatics 102: 24–37. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). Yet, co-occurring linguistic elements and accompanying paralinguistic features may somehow determine their outputs. These processes are also seen as a necessary step prior to obtaining a fully propositional form that may capture what the speaker says and be evaluated in terms of truthfulness. Indeed, context-independent, lexically encoded concepts are believed to simply contribute some sort of raw or skeletal material requiring occasion-specific inferential fleshing out. Finally, these processes are portrayed as not mutually exclusive, but complementary. Arriving at intended meaning may involve restricting a concept in some respects while simultaneously loosening it in others, as in the case of metaphor (Wilson and Carston 2006Wilson, Deirdre, and Robyn Carston 2006 “Metaphor, Relevance and the ‘Emergent Property’ Issue.” Mind & Language 21 (3): 404–433. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 2007 2007 “A Unitary Approach to Lexical Pragmatics: Relevance, Inference and Ad Hoc Concepts.” In Pragmatics, ed. by Noel Burton-Roberts, 230–259. Basingstoke: Palgrave. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Sperber and Wilson 2008 2008 “A Deflationary Account of Metaphors.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Metaphor and Thought, ed. by Raymond W. Gibbs, 84–105. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar).

The output of these processes is labelled an ad hoc concept. This is described as a more specific, context-sensitive conceptual representation which is built on the grounds of the conceptual material encoded or activated by a content word. It is created during the parallel adjustment of explicit and implicit speaker-intended meaning, on the basis of expectations of relevance, possible developments of an utterance’s explicature and hypothesised contextual implications. Due to its specificity, and perhaps uniqueness, an ad hoc concept may be a one-off, purpose-built mental entity differing in some guise from the context-independent, lexically encoded concept. It is likely to have a short lifespan in an individual’s cognitive activity, but it could also stabilise and spread throughout a community of language users.

Identification of these lexical pragmatic processes has facilitated alternative accounts of non-literal uses of language, figures of speech or tropes, such as metaphor, metonymy, hyperbole or simile (Papafragou 1996Papafragou, Anna 1996 “On Metonymy.” Lingua 99 (4): 169–195. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Carston 2002b 2002b “Metaphor, Ad Hoc Concepts and Word Meaning – More Questions than Answers.” UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 14: 83–105.Google Scholar, 2010a 2010a “Lexical Pragmatics, Ad Hoc Concepts and Metaphor: From a Relevance Theory Perspective.” Italian Journal of Linguistics 22 (1): 153–180.Google Scholar, 2010b 2010b “Metaphor: Ad Hoc Concepts, Literal Meaning and Mental Images.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 110 (3): 295–321. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 2012 2012 “Metaphor and the Literal/Nonliteral Distinction.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. by Keith Allan, and Kasia M. Jaszczolt, 469–492. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Vega Moreno 2007Vega Moreno, Rosa E. 2007Creativity and Convention: The Pragmatics of Everyday Figurative Speech. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Wałaszewska 2010Wałaszewska, Ewa 2010 “Simile in Relevance Theory: Towards an Alternative Account.” Acta Philologica 38: 13–19.Google Scholar; Carston and Wearing 2012Carston, Robyn, and Catherine Wearing 2012 “Metaphor, Hyperbole and Simile: A Pragmatic Approach.” Language and Cognition 3 (2): 283–312. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 2015 2015 “Hyperbolic Language and Its Relation to Metaphor and Irony.” Journal of Pragmatics 79: 79–92. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Rubio-Fernández et al. 2013Rubio-Fernández, Paula, Catherine Wearing, and Robyn Carston 2013 “How Metaphor and Hyperbole Differ: An Empirical Investigation of the Relevance-Theoretic Account of Loose Use.” UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 25: 20–45.Google Scholar, 2015 2015 “Metaphor and Hyperbole: Testing the Continuity Hypothesis.” Metaphor and Symbol 30 (1): 24–40. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Jodłowiec and Piskorska 2015Jodłowiec, Maria, and Agnieszka Piskorska 2015 “Metonymy Revisited: Towards a New Relevance-Theoretic Account.” Intercultural Pragmatics 12 (2): 161–187. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). With remarkable differences from cognitive-linguistic ones (Wilson 2011b 2011b “Parallels and Differences in the Treatment of Metaphor in Relevance Theory and Cognitive Linguistics.” Intercultural Pragmatics 8 (2): 177–196. DOI logoGoogle Scholar), these accounts replace previous relevance-theoretic ones surmising that the increase of cognitive effort caused by such loose language uses is intended in the interest of yielding weak implicatures (Sperber and Wilson 1986Sperber, Dan, and Deirdre Wilson 1986Relevance: Communication and Cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar, 1995 1995Relevance: Communication and Cognition. 2nd ed. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar, 2008 2008 “A Deflationary Account of Metaphors.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Metaphor and Thought, ed. by Raymond W. Gibbs, 84–105. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar).88.In turn, those accounts had replaced the Gricean approach relying on blatant violations of expected norms of truthfulness, informativeness or relevance (Grice 1957Grice, Herbert P. 1957 “Meaning.” Philosophical Review 66: 377–388. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). Moreover, the relevance-theoretic account of ad hoc concept construction boosted understanding of some lexical phenomena when it comes to researching children’s speech (Wałaszewska 2011 2011 “Broadening and Narrowing in Lexical Development: How Relevance Theory Can Account for Children’s Overextensions and Underextensions.” Journal of Pragmatics 43 (1): 314–326. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 2020 2020 “Category Extension as a Variety of Loose Use.” In Relevance Theory, Figuration, and Continuity in Pragmatics, ed. by Agnieszka Piskorska, 25–43. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI logoGoogle Scholar), interpretation of novel metaphors (Wearing 2014 2014 “Interpreting Novel Metaphors.” International Review of Pragmatics 6 (1): 78–102. DOI logoGoogle Scholar), semantic change (Clark 2016Clark, Billy 2016 “Relevance Theory and Language Change.” Lingua 175–176: 139–153. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Padilla Cruz 2017 2017 “On the Origin and Meaning of Secondary Interjections: A Relevance-Theoretic Proposal.” In Applications of Relevance Theory: From Discourse to Morphemes, ed. by Agnieszka Piskorska, and Ewa Wałaszewska, 299–326. Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.Google Scholar), how insults work (Padilla Cruz 2019 2019 “Qualifying Insults, Offensive Epithets, Slurs and Expressive Expletives: A Relevance-Theoretic Approach.” Journal of Language Aggression and Conflict 7 (2): 156–181. DOI logoGoogle Scholar), acquisition of metaphor and metonymy (Falkum 2019Falkum, Ingrid L. 2019 “Metaphor and Metonymy in Acquisition: A Relevance Theoretic Perspective.” In Relevance: Pragmatics and Interpretation, ed. by Kate Scott, Robyn Carston, and Billy Clark, 205–217. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar), L2 metaphor comprehension (Ifantidou 2019 2019 “Relevance and Metaphor Understanding in a Second Language.” In Relevance: Pragmatics and Interpretation, ed. by Kate Scott, Robyn Carston, and Billy Clark, 218–230. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Ifantidou and Hatzidaki 2019Ifantidou, Elly, and Anna Hatzidaki 2019 “Metaphor Comprehension in L2: Meaning, Images and Emotions.” Journal of Pragmatics 149: 78–90. DOI logoGoogle Scholar), use of metaphors in certain genres (Ifantidou 2009 2009 “Newspapers Headlines and Relevance: Ad Hoc Concepts in Ad Hoc Contexts.” Journal of Pragmatics 41: 699–720. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Unger 2019Unger, Christoph 2019 “Allegory in Relation to Metaphor and Irony.” In Relevance: Pragmatics and Interpretation, ed. by Kate Scott, Robyn Carston, and Billy Clark, 240–252. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Mateo and Yus 2021Mateo, José, and Francisco Yus 2021 “Ad Hoc Concepts in Humorous Financial Metaphors: A Pragmatic Approach.” In Metaphor in Economics and Specialised Discourse, ed. by José Mateo, and Francisco Yus. Bern: Peter Lang. DOI logoGoogle Scholar), their helpfulness in therapeutic discourse (Needham-Didsbury 2014Needham-Didsbury, Isabelle 2014 “Metaphor in Psychotherapeutic Discourse: Implications for Utterance Interpretation.” Poznan Studies in Contemporary Linguistics 50 (1): 75–98. DOI logoGoogle Scholar) or the challenges that they pose to autistic people (Wearing 2010Wearing, Catherine 2010 “Autism, Metaphor and Relevance Theory.” Mind & Language 25 (2): 196–216. DOI logoGoogle Scholar).99.Carston (2013a 2013a “Word Meaning, What Is Said and Explicature.” In What Is Said and What Is Not, ed. by Carlo Penco, and Filippo Domaneschi, 175–204. Stanford: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar, 2013b 2013b “Implicature, Explicature, and Truth-Theoretic Semantics.” In The Semantics-Pragmatics Boundary in Philosophy, ed. by Maite Ezcurdia and Robert J. Stainton, 261–283. Peterborough: Broadview Press.Google Scholar, 2016 2016 “The Heterogeneity of Procedural Meaning.” Lingua 175–176: 154–166. DOI logoGoogle Scholar) has considered a more radical possibility: conceptual eliminativism. Accordingly, open-class words might not be associated to specific conceptual material in a stable manner, but rather open some sort of mental file subsuming varied information, or create some sort of address or label in memory connecting varied information.

The claim that ad hoc concept construction is not mandated by any element has recently been revisited (Padilla Cruz 2022a 2022a “Is Free Enrichment always Free? Revisiting Ad Hoc Concept Construction.” Journal of Pragmatics 187: 130–143. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). In inflectional languages, morphemes like the diminutive and the augmentative may trigger adjustments resulting in particularised conceptual representations. Thus, addition of the diminutive to casa (‘house’) in (15) below could lead to the formation of casa*/house*, which would refer not necessarily to a small dwelling, but to a poor, seedy, rundown and gloomy one (Padilla Cruz 2020 2020 “Towards a Relevance-Theoretic Approach to the Diminutive Morpheme.” Russian Journal of Linguistics 24 (4): 774–795. DOI logoGoogle Scholar):

(15)

Vive en una casucha en mitad del campo.

‘He lives in a house[+DIM] in the middle of the countryside’.

Similarly, the definite and indefinite articles, demonstratives and possessives, which occupy the determiner position; qualifying adjectives, as well as lexical items and phrasal or sentential constituents fulfilling adjectival functions; expressive expletives like damned or bleeding, and evidential participles like supposed or alleged, may all give rise to more concrete conceptual entities (Padilla Cruz 2022a 2022a “Is Free Enrichment always Free? Revisiting Ad Hoc Concept Construction.” Journal of Pragmatics 187: 130–143. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 2022b 2022b “On the Interpretation of Utterances with Expressive Expletives.” Pragmatics & Cognition 28 (2): 252–276. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, in press In press. “Ad Hoc Concepts, Affective Attitude and Epistemic Stance.” Pragmatics & Cognition.). Accordingly, the indefinite article would modulate man in (16) as denoting an unknown male person; the adjective in (17) would create an idiosyncratic representation alluding to a special, elegant, well-equipped, comfortable, cosy accommodation; the expletive in (18) would give rise to guy* referring to a contemptuous, reprehensible, foolish, imprudent person, and the participle in (19) would finetune extortioner as something paraphrasable as ‘the man who is supposed to have extorted people because someone saw him doing so’:

(16)

A man is entering the shop.

(17)

We booked a boutique hotel in the centre.

(18)

That fucking guy is not wearing a facemask!

(19)

Supposed extortioner tried last week.

Still, lexical repetitions and rewording could adjust already activated conceptual representations by delimiting, nuancing or enriching their denotational spaces. Thus, the repetition of the adjective in (20) may flesh out the concept in question as alluding to an exceptional, unexpected or shocking type of richness, while the replacement in (21) may refine the concept associated with the characteristic attributed to the essay as referring to messiness or nonsense.

(20)

John is rich, rich, rich.

(21)

Martha’s essay is confusing… messy.

Just as these morphological, lexical and phrasal elements and stylistic choices may trigger and somehow determine the output of ad hoc concept formation in precise manners, paralanguage could also contribute to this lexical pragmatic process. Paralinguistic clues and features might overtly indicate that context-sensitive and specific notions are necessary in order to grasp speaker-intended meaning and assist hearers in their formation. Since they are considered to act as pointers and constrainers of this pragmatic process, these behaviours will be generically referred to as ‘markers’ or ‘indicators’.

5.Paralinguistic markers of ad hoc concepts

The idea that paralanguage affects lexical pragmatic processes, thus contributing to the explicit truth-conditional content of utterances and guiding hearers to certain conclusions, is not at all new and was already entertained by Wharton (2009 2009Pragmatics and Non-Verbal Communication. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 51 and ch. 6). What follows seeks to illustrate the contribution of the heterogeneous behaviours falling within paralanguage to ad hoc concept construction, an issue that has not been exhaustively tackled thus far. In fact, it is not clear if all of them contribute to it or if they do so in the same fashion.

5.1Interjections

Interjections occupy distinct positions along a cline ranging from a conceptual pole to a procedural one, from cases of meaning nn to mere cases of showing (Padilla Cruz 2009aPadilla Cruz, Manuel 2009a “Might Interjections Encode Concepts? More Questions than Answers.” Łodź Papers in Pragmatics 5 (2): 241–270.Google Scholar; Wharton 2016 2016 “That Bloody So-and-so Has Retired: Expressives Revisited.” Lingua 175–176: 20–35. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). In the case of expressive or emotive interjections, the origin, reason or cause of the psychological state that the speaker voices may be mentally represented in conceptual terms. Just as any lexically encoded concept may be specified and can refer to (more) particular conditions, instantiations, experiences, etc., the concept denoting the origin, reason or cause of a psychological state may also be enriched or adjusted. Its encyclopaedic entry may receive information about the attitudes, feelings and/or emotions that its referent causes. If that information was already present, it could be given more prominence and made essential, albeit momentarily, thus adjusting the concept.

Consider (22) below. The interjection in the second response alone could obviously allow the mother to attain some effect pertaining to her son’s elatedness, delight or euphoria because of the dish that he is about to enjoy. It would thus prompt her to construct the higher-level explicature in (23).

(22)

Son:What are we having for dinner?
Mother:Soup.
Son: Oh/Wow/Yay, soup!

(23)

[sonx is happy*/elated*/delighted*/euphoric* [there is soup*/to have* soup*]]

Additional available information could help finetune the lexically encoded concept as denoting a type of tasty traditional soup made with noodles and wild mushrooms. The by-product of this process could in turn enjoin the mother to deduce weak implicatures to the effect that her son loves that type of soup, prefers it over other soups or likes having it only for dinner. But deliberate and ostensive production of the interjection might alternatively enrich, or further narrow down, soup on the grounds of information concerning the son’s likes, preferences, longings or feelings. Had the interjection argh been intentionally added, the information enriching it, or facilitating its restriction, would obviously have regarded opposite feelings. Regardless of the direction its specification takes, the creation of soup* would also entitle the mother to derive an array of (weak) implicatures satisfying her expectations of relevance.

Consider now (24).

(24)

Ow/Ouch, that hurts!

The interjection could of course be proffered instinctively and involuntarily, and amount to some audible symptom of the speaker’s pain. Given the proposition expressed by the utterance that the interjection accompanies, it could even be redundant, as the speaker’s feelings, or her informative intention, would be evident from that proposition. In this case, the interjection would provide further acoustic evidence securing the construction of some intended attitudinal description:

(25)

[The speaker feels pain].

But the interjection could also be produced deliberately and ostensively. In this case, it could help the hearer specify the concept hurt as referring not to an average pain, but to a rather intense, sharp, unbearable or inhuman pain, or to a pain that hurts in an unexpected, astonishing, overwhelming or shocking manner. Such a specification may be accomplished through an addition of the corresponding information to the concept’s encyclopaedic entry or by rendering that information definitional.

Although expressive interjections could contribute to lexical pragmatic processes in this fashion, conative interjections would obviously not trigger or impact lexical pragmatic processes. Their interpretation would be contingent on (an) inference(s) yielding some propositional or non-propositional effect concerning the speaker’s desire(s) or the action that she wants the hearer to perform. In essence, conative interjections are orders and, as such, they present a state of affairs as desirable from the speaker’s perspective (Sperber and Wilson 1986Sperber, Dan, and Deirdre Wilson 1986Relevance: Communication and Cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar, 1995 1995Relevance: Communication and Cognition. 2nd ed. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar) and signal the individual expected or intended to bring it about. Accordingly, a conative interjection like (26a) would give rise to some sort of speech-act description like (26b).

(26)
  1. Shhh! (addressed to an individual who is speaking during a lecture)

  2. [The speaker wants me to shut up].

5.2Prosodic/suprasegmental markers

Depending on whether their interpretation is contingent on inference or biological codes, prosodic inputs may be sorted out as: natural signs, if they are interpreted inferentially; natural signals, if their interpretation involves decoding; and linguistic signals, if they are jointly interpreted through inference and decoding (Wharton 2012 2012 “Pragmatics and Prosody.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. by Keith Allan, and Kasia M. Jaszczolt, 567–584. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 573–574). Their different places in the showing–meaning nn continuum make them “fall within the domain of pragmatics and contribute to a speaker’s meaning” (Wharton 2012 2012 “Pragmatics and Prosody.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. by Keith Allan, and Kasia M. Jaszczolt, 567–584. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 576). Concerning lexical pragmatic processes, prosodic inputs have also been claimed to interact with lexical items so as to finetune their meaning (Wharton 2009 2009Pragmatics and Non-Verbal Communication. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 141–142). However, it has not been duly illustrated whether all prosodic inputs do so and how.

When intentionally exploited, pitch may also delineate concepts. Suppose someone was comfortably sitting in their dining room while having a snack, and uttered either of the following with the nominal element overtly pronounced with low pitch:

(27)

This is cheese!

(28)

I love wine.

Pitch lowness would exhibit some (perhaps) ineffable psychological state – e.g., delight, pleasure, enjoyment – which the speaker experiences as a consequence of having either of the products she mentions. It would point the hearer to some notional space connected with such a state, which is in turn caused by the particular type or brand of the product that the speaker is consuming, its (good or outstanding) quality, texture, flavour or notes, how it is cut or the fact that it is served at a certain temperature. Thus, pitch lowness would openly signal that it is not cheese or wine in general that are meant, but those of the particular type, quality, texture, flavour, notes, etc., which the speaker is having at that moment. Consequently, pitch would ostensively encourage the hearer to narrow down cheese and wine in those directions. This narrowing would require enriching the concepts’ encyclopaedic entries with propositional or non-propositional information – images, impressions, etc. – about the products’ intended characteristics and perhaps endowing some of that information, albeit temporarily, with a definitional status. In any case, once the activated concepts are adjusted, the hearer, depending on his expectations of relevance, would be entitled to derive varied implicatures, for instance, to the effect that the cheese or wine in question are those that the speaker would recommend or have for a special occasion.

Contrastive stress is considered to involve additional cognitive effort (Sperber and Wilson 1986Sperber, Dan, and Deirdre Wilson 1986Relevance: Communication and Cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar, 1995 1995Relevance: Communication and Cognition. 2nd ed. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar; Wilson and Wharton 2006Wilson, Deirdre, and Tim Wharton 2006 “Relevance and Prosody.” Journal of Pragmatics 38 (10): 1559–1579. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Wharton 2009 2009Pragmatics and Non-Verbal Communication. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 2012 2012 “Pragmatics and Prosody.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. by Keith Allan, and Kasia M. Jaszczolt, 567–584. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Madella 2020Madella, Pauline 2020 “Prosodic Pointing: From Pragmatic Awareness to Pragmatic Competence in Chinese Hearers of L2 English.” PhD diss. University of Brighton.). Just as additional effort often warrants further cognitive benefits, added articulatory effort or strength may frequently be a clue to particularised meaning. Hence, this stress may also work as a prosodic stimulus that can be ostensively exploited. When falling upon a word, contrastive stress could also accomplish a signalling or highlighting function, thus openly indicating a peculiar speaker-intended meaning. Surely, in Examples (27) and (28) above, cheese and wine could also have received this type of prosodic prominence. It would ostensively mark that the lexically encoded concepts certainly need delimiting on the grounds of certain information, thus making it possible for the hearer to grasp the speakers’ meaning. Contrastive stress then becomes, in Madella’s (2020)Madella, Pauline 2020 “Prosodic Pointing: From Pragmatic Awareness to Pragmatic Competence in Chinese Hearers of L2 English.” PhD diss. University of Brighton. terms, a prosodic pointing device.

A similar pointing function may also be ascribed to pace or tempo. Nuanced concepts may arise as a result of the speed at which, not necessarily a whole sentence, but a sole word is articulated. Consider (29).

(29)

Martha came slowly.

If the speaker pronounced the adverb very slowly, with vowel elongation in the tonic syllable, as if mimetically replicating the speed with which Martha walked, pace would generate slowly* as a way of capturing an astonishingly placid speed, an exasperatingly tranquil one or one below some standard. It could even generate certain images picturing how Martha walked or trigger certain sensations. In addition to pointing to the need of a specific notion, pace would also iconically show the direction that its creation should follow, thus working as an iconic prosodic pointing device.

Intonation, in contrast, does not seem to play this role. In the dialogue in (22) above, the son’s response could have simply been soup. Although delimiting the actual value(s) of the tone employed could be difficult, the son would not have invited the mother to shape an occasion-specific conceptual representation. Rather, his tone would have assisted her in the construction of (a) specific actional or attitudinal description(s) and given rise to non-propositional effects. Hence, intonation is perhaps the sole prosodic input that retains a pure role as constrainer of higher-level explicatures and does not enact lexical pragmatic processes by itself.

5.3Gestural markers

The spontaneous nature of proper gesticulation perhaps deprives it of the pointing function attributed to some prosodic inputs, but other gesture types may fulfil it, thus becoming pointing devices, albeit visual. Language-like gestures such as head nods, raised eyebrows or finger or hand pointing, as well as expressions like smiles or grimaces, which can be deliberately made as a particular word is uttered, may certainly entitle the hearer to contrive an idiosyncratic conceptual representation. For example, a smile of delight and eyes (half-)shut will encourage the hearer to restrict cheese in (27) and wine in (28) as referring to quality cheese/wine or products of a brand that the speaker likes. A grimace of disgust or a gesture of disappointment, in contrast, would take that adjustment through a distinct route. Similarly, a gesture illustrating the shape or largeness of the referent of a noun could finetune the activated concept on the basis of the respective information or even prompt the hearer to forge some mental image.

Moreover, the mimetic character of pantomimes and the properties of emblems could even steer lexical pragmatic processes in more precise manners, thus becoming iconic or mimetic visual pointers. In (29) the speaker’s openly placing her bent arms in front of the chest, hands with palms up, and ostensively moving them up and down repeatedly and very slowly would add supportive evidence for the ideas that Martha’s speed was slower than average or irritatingly slow, on the basis of which slowly* would be delineated. And something similar would happen in the case of an emblem like the Italian gesture for taste appreciation, pleasure and/or enjoyment, if the person doing it ostentatiously twisted the finger touching her cheek rapidly or vividly.

6.Conclusion

This paper has shown that paralanguage may signal and direct ad hoc concept construction. This involves admitting that paralinguistic inputs may work as pointers of this lexical pragmatic process when they are deliberately produced. Depending on their nature and the channel that they exploit, two sorts of pointers in addition to interjections could also be distinguished: prosodic and gestural. This has clear implications for the current relevance-theoretic approaches to paralanguage and lexical pragmatics.

The first of them has to do with the freedom from linguistic mandate of ad hoc concept formation: in addition to being triggered by certain linguistic elements, it could also be mandated by paralinguistic inputs. However, among prosodic ones, only pitch, contrastive stress and pace would ostensibly provide natural evidence for the relevance of occasion-specific concepts, as the role of intonation would be limited to facilitating speech-act or affective-attitude descriptions. Among gestural inputs, language-like gestures, pantomimes and emblems could overtly behave as visual pointers, since the spontaneous nature of proper gesticulation generally prevents it from doing so. Pantomimes and emblems, furthermore, could mimetically suggest the direction in which the expected output must be constructed. Future research, nevertheless, should check the exhaustiveness of the list of paralinguistic inputs triggering occasion-specific concepts and perhaps incorporate additional ones from languages or varieties belonging to diverse (sub-)families.

A second implication affects the contribution of paralanguage to comprehension and its procedural meaning. Relevance theorists have thus far treated paralanguage as giving rise to actional and attitudinal descriptions. However, part of attitude- or emotion-related information may originate during lexical pragmatic processes as a result of the occurrence of specific paralinguistic inputs. These would make it manifest and entitle hearers to store it in the corresponding entries of activated conceptual representations, thus enriching and further delimiting them, albeit momentarily, with a view to creating a more specific, perhaps one-off conceptual entity. If so, the procedure that paralanguage encodes need not be solely connected with the construction of higher-level explicatures, but could be more loosely characterised as enabling the representation of attitude- or emotion-related information that may feature in a higher-level explicature or in a conceptual representation.

Notes

1.Following a relevance-theoretic convention, reference to the speaker is made through the third person singular feminine pronoun, while reference to the hearer is made through the masculine pronoun.
2.Still, other interjections may be phatic (Ameka 1992b 1992b “The Meaning of Phatic and Conative Interjections.” Journal of Pragmatics 18 (2–3): 245–271. DOI logoGoogle Scholar) or refer to verbal performance, manage conversation and work as discourse markers (Clark and Fox Tree 2002Clark, Herbert H., and Jean E. Fox Tree 2002 “Using uh and um in Spontaneous Speaking.” Cognition 84 (1): 73–11. DOI logoGoogle Scholar).
3.For Damásio (1994)Dámasio, António 1994Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason and the Human Brain. New York: Avon.Google Scholar, such elementary emotions are happiness, sadness, anger, fear and disgust, while Goleman (1995)Goleman, Daniel 1995Emotional Intelligence. New York: Bantam Books.Google Scholar also adds enjoyment, love, surprise and shame.
4.Fully determinate meaning would require words to attain absolute explicitness of speaker-intended meaning (Sperber and Wilson 2015 2015 “Beyond Speaker’s Meaning.” Croatian Journal of Philosophy 15 (44): 117–149.Google Scholar, 135–136).
5.Expressed attitudes, feelings and emotions have physiological reflexes that enable them to be experienced, and therefore characterised, with a certain intensity, vividness or temporal duration. They also have psychological correlates and may be mentally represented. But they originate as responses to phenomena or states of affairs (Damásio 1994Dámasio, António 1994Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason and the Human Brain. New York: Avon.Google Scholar). The non-translational content of interjections could also amount to procedures facilitating identification of the cause(s) of those reactions. To put it differently, the procedures that interjections would pack could signal the phenomenon or state of affairs that makes the speaker feel, or undergo, the state that she verbalises by means of an interjection (Padilla Cruz 2009b 2009b “Towards an Alternative Relevance-Theoretic Approach to Interjections.” International Review of Pragmatics 1 (1): 182–206. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). Like indexicals (Wilkins 1992Wilkins, David P. 1992 “Interjections and Deictics.” Journal of Pragmatics 18 (2–3): 119–158. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 1995 1995 “Expanding the Traditional Category of Deictic Elements: Interjections as Deictics.” In Deixis in Narrative: A Cognitive Science Perspective, ed. by Judith F. Duchan, Gail A. Bruder, and Lynne E. Hewitt, 359–386. Hillsdale: LEA.Google Scholar), interjections would thus point to the origin of, or reason for, a felt and voiced psychological state, of which they would somehow be a symptom (Rosier 2000Rosier, Laurence 2000 “Interjection, subjectivité, expressivité et discourse rapport à l’écrit: Petits effets d’un petit discourse.” Cahiers de Praxématique 34: 19–49. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Schourup 2001Schourup, Lawrence 2001 “Rethinking well .” Journal of Pragmatics 33 (7): 1025–1060. DOI logoGoogle Scholar; Kleiber 2006Kleiber, Georges 2006 “Sémiotique de l’interjection.” Langages 161 (1): 10–23. DOI logoGoogle Scholar). However, to Wilkins (1992Wilkins, David P. 1992 “Interjections and Deictics.” Journal of Pragmatics 18 (2–3): 119–158. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 1995 1995 “Expanding the Traditional Category of Deictic Elements: Interjections as Deictics.” In Deixis in Narrative: A Cognitive Science Perspective, ed. by Judith F. Duchan, Gail A. Bruder, and Lynne E. Hewitt, 359–386. Hillsdale: LEA.Google Scholar), the indexical nature of interjections would make them subcategorise hidden or covert referential slots in an underlying proposition, which must be filled with extralinguistic information. This claim is not consistent with some relevance-theoretic postulates on mutual parallel adjustment and free enrichment (Carston 2000 2000 “Explicature and Semantics.” UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 12: 1–44.Google Scholar).
6.As supportive evidence, Wharton (2012 2012 “Pragmatics and Prosody.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. by Keith Allan, and Kasia M. Jaszczolt, 567–584. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar, 573) mentions that primates and humans possess a neural machinery enabling facial recognition and processing of facial expressions.
7.Following another relevance-theoretic convention, concepts are notated in small caps.
8.In turn, those accounts had replaced the Gricean approach relying on blatant violations of expected norms of truthfulness, informativeness or relevance (Grice 1957Grice, Herbert P. 1957 “Meaning.” Philosophical Review 66: 377–388. DOI logoGoogle Scholar).
9.Carston (2013a 2013a “Word Meaning, What Is Said and Explicature.” In What Is Said and What Is Not, ed. by Carlo Penco, and Filippo Domaneschi, 175–204. Stanford: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar, 2013b 2013b “Implicature, Explicature, and Truth-Theoretic Semantics.” In The Semantics-Pragmatics Boundary in Philosophy, ed. by Maite Ezcurdia and Robert J. Stainton, 261–283. Peterborough: Broadview Press.Google Scholar, 2016 2016 “The Heterogeneity of Procedural Meaning.” Lingua 175–176: 154–166. DOI logoGoogle Scholar) has considered a more radical possibility: conceptual eliminativism. Accordingly, open-class words might not be associated to specific conceptual material in a stable manner, but rather open some sort of mental file subsuming varied information, or create some sort of address or label in memory connecting varied information.

References

Aijmer, Karin
2004 “Interjections in a Contrastive Perspective.” In Emotion in Dialogic Interaction: Advances in the Complex, ed. by Edda Weigand, 99–120. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Ameka, Felix K.
1992a “Interjections: The Universal yet Neglected Part of Speech.” Journal of Pragmatics 18 (2–3): 101–118. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
1992b “The Meaning of Phatic and Conative Interjections.” Journal of Pragmatics 18 (2–3): 245–271. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2006 “Interjections.” In Encyclopaedia of Language and Linguistics, ed. by Keith Brown, 743–746. Amsterdam: Elsevier. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Barsalou, Lawrence W.
1983 “Ad Hoc Categories.” Memory & Cognition 11: 211–227. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
1987 “The Instability of Graded Structure in Concepts.” In Concepts and Conceptual Development: Ecological and Intellectual Factors in Categorization, ed. by Ulric Neisser, 101–140. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bolinger, Dwight
1983 “Where Does Intonation Belong?Journal of Semantics 2 (2): 101–120. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Carston, Robyn
1996 “Enrichment and Loosening: Complementary Processes in Deriving the Proposition Expressed.” UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 8: 61–88.Google Scholar
2000 “Explicature and Semantics.” UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 12: 1–44.Google Scholar
2002aThoughts and Utterances. The Pragmatics of Explicit Communication. Oxford: Blackwell. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2002b “Metaphor, Ad Hoc Concepts and Word Meaning – More Questions than Answers.” UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 14: 83–105.Google Scholar
2010a “Lexical Pragmatics, Ad Hoc Concepts and Metaphor: From a Relevance Theory Perspective.” Italian Journal of Linguistics 22 (1): 153–180.Google Scholar
2010b “Metaphor: Ad Hoc Concepts, Literal Meaning and Mental Images.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 110 (3): 295–321. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2012 “Metaphor and the Literal/Nonliteral Distinction.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. by Keith Allan, and Kasia M. Jaszczolt, 469–492. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2013a “Word Meaning, What Is Said and Explicature.” In What Is Said and What Is Not, ed. by Carlo Penco, and Filippo Domaneschi, 175–204. Stanford: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
2013b “Implicature, Explicature, and Truth-Theoretic Semantics.” In The Semantics-Pragmatics Boundary in Philosophy, ed. by Maite Ezcurdia and Robert J. Stainton, 261–283. Peterborough: Broadview Press.Google Scholar
2016 “The Heterogeneity of Procedural Meaning.” Lingua 175–176: 154–166. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Carston, Robyn, and Catherine Wearing
2012 “Metaphor, Hyperbole and Simile: A Pragmatic Approach.” Language and Cognition 3 (2): 283–312. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2015 “Hyperbolic Language and Its Relation to Metaphor and Irony.” Journal of Pragmatics 79: 79–92. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Clark, Billy
2016 “Relevance Theory and Language Change.” Lingua 175–176: 139–153. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Clark, Billy, and Geoff Lindsey
1990 “Intonation, Grammar and Utterance Interpretation: Evidence from English Exclamatory-Inversions.” UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 2: 32–51.Google Scholar
Clark, Herbert H., and Jean E. Fox Tree
2002 “Using uh and um in Spontaneous Speaking.” Cognition 84 (1): 73–11. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Couper-Kuhlen, Elizabeth
1986An Introduction to English Prosody. Tübingen: Niemeyer.Google Scholar
Dámasio, António
1994Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason and the Human Brain. New York: Avon.Google Scholar
Escandell-Vidal, Victoria
1998 “Intonation and Procedural Encoding: The Case of Spanish Interrogatives.” In Current Issues in Relevance Theory, ed. by Villy Rouchota, and Andreas H. Jucker, 169–203. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Falkum, Ingrid L.
2019 “Metaphor and Metonymy in Acquisition: A Relevance Theoretic Perspective.” In Relevance: Pragmatics and Interpretation, ed. by Kate Scott, Robyn Carston, and Billy Clark, 205–217. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Fodor, Jerry A.
1983The Modularity of Mind. Cambridge: MIT Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Fretheim, Thorstein
1998 “Intonation and the Procedural Encoding of Attributed Thoughts: The Case of Norwegian Interrogatives.” In Current Issues in Relevance Theory, ed. by Villy Rouchota, and Andreas H. Jucker, 205–236. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Goleman, Daniel
1995Emotional Intelligence. New York: Bantam Books.Google Scholar
Grice, Herbert P.
1957 “Meaning.” Philosophical Review 66: 377–388. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Gussenhoven, Carlos
2004The Phonology of Tone and Intonation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Hall, Alison
2017 “Lexical Pragmatics, Explicature and Ad Hoc Concepts.” In Semantics and Pragmatics: Drawing a Line, ed. by Ilse Depraetere, and Raphael Salkie, 55–100. Cham: Springer. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Halliday, M. A. K.
1967Intonation and Grammar in British English. The Hague: Mouton. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Hirschberg, Julia, and Gregory Ward
1995 “The Interpretation of the High-Rise Question Contour in English.” Journal of Pragmatics 24 (4): 407–412. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
House, Jill
1989 “The Relevance of Intonation?UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 1: 3–17.Google Scholar
1990 “Intonation Structures and Pragmatic Interpretation.” In Studies in the Pronunciation of English: A Commemorative Volume in Honour of A. C. Gimson, ed. by Susan Ramsaran, 38–57. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Ifantidou, Elly
1992 “Sentential Adverbs and Relevance.” UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 4: 193–214.Google Scholar
2009 “Newspapers Headlines and Relevance: Ad Hoc Concepts in Ad Hoc Contexts.” Journal of Pragmatics 41: 699–720. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2019 “Relevance and Metaphor Understanding in a Second Language.” In Relevance: Pragmatics and Interpretation, ed. by Kate Scott, Robyn Carston, and Billy Clark, 218–230. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Ifantidou, Elly, and Anna Hatzidaki
2019 “Metaphor Comprehension in L2: Meaning, Images and Emotions.” Journal of Pragmatics 149: 78–90. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Imai, Kunihiko
1998 “Intonation and Relevance.” In Relevance Theory: Applications and Implications, ed. by Robyn Carston and Seiji Uchida, 69–86. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Jary, Mark
2016 “Rethinking Explicit Utterance Content.” Journal of Pragmatics 102: 24–37. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Jodłowiec, Maria, and Agnieszka Piskorska
2015 “Metonymy Revisited: Towards a New Relevance-Theoretic Account.” Intercultural Pragmatics 12 (2): 161–187. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Kendon, Adam
1988 “How Gestures Can Become like Words?” In Cross-Cultural Perspectives in Nonverbal Communication, ed. by Fernando Poyatos, 131–141. Toronto: Hogrefe.Google Scholar
2004Gesture: Visible Action as Utterance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Kleiber, Georges
2006 “Sémiotique de l’interjection.” Langages 161 (1): 10–23. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Ladd, Robert
1996Intonational Phonology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Madella, Pauline
2020 “Prosodic Pointing: From Pragmatic Awareness to Pragmatic Competence in Chinese Hearers of L2 English.” PhD diss. University of Brighton.
Mateo, José, and Francisco Yus
2021 “Ad Hoc Concepts in Humorous Financial Metaphors: A Pragmatic Approach.” In Metaphor in Economics and Specialised Discourse, ed. by José Mateo, and Francisco Yus. Bern: Peter Lang. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
McNeill, David
1992Hand and Mind: What Gestures Reveal about Thought. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Needham-Didsbury, Isabelle
2014 “Metaphor in Psychotherapeutic Discourse: Implications for Utterance Interpretation.” Poznan Studies in Contemporary Linguistics 50 (1): 75–98. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
O’Connell, Daniel C., and Sabine Kowal
2005 “Where Do Interjections Come from? A Psycholinguistic Analysis of Shaw’s Pygmalion .” Journal of Psycholinguistic Research 34 (5): 497–514. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Padilla Cruz, Manuel
2009a “Might Interjections Encode Concepts? More Questions than Answers.” Łodź Papers in Pragmatics 5 (2): 241–270.Google Scholar
2009b “Towards an Alternative Relevance-Theoretic Approach to Interjections.” International Review of Pragmatics 1 (1): 182–206. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2017 “On the Origin and Meaning of Secondary Interjections: A Relevance-Theoretic Proposal.” In Applications of Relevance Theory: From Discourse to Morphemes, ed. by Agnieszka Piskorska, and Ewa Wałaszewska, 299–326. Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.Google Scholar
2019 “Qualifying Insults, Offensive Epithets, Slurs and Expressive Expletives: A Relevance-Theoretic Approach.” Journal of Language Aggression and Conflict 7 (2): 156–181. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2020 “Towards a Relevance-Theoretic Approach to the Diminutive Morpheme.” Russian Journal of Linguistics 24 (4): 774–795. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2022a “Is Free Enrichment always Free? Revisiting Ad Hoc Concept Construction.” Journal of Pragmatics 187: 130–143. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2022b “On the Interpretation of Utterances with Expressive Expletives.” Pragmatics & Cognition 28 (2): 252–276. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
In press. “Ad Hoc Concepts, Affective Attitude and Epistemic Stance.” Pragmatics & Cognition.
Papafragou, Anna
1996 “On Metonymy.” Lingua 99 (4): 169–195. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Rosier, Laurence
2000 “Interjection, subjectivité, expressivité et discourse rapport à l’écrit: Petits effets d’un petit discourse.” Cahiers de Praxématique 34: 19–49. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Rubio-Fernández, Paula, Catherine Wearing, and Robyn Carston
2013 “How Metaphor and Hyperbole Differ: An Empirical Investigation of the Relevance-Theoretic Account of Loose Use.” UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 25: 20–45.Google Scholar
2015 “Metaphor and Hyperbole: Testing the Continuity Hypothesis.” Metaphor and Symbol 30 (1): 24–40. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Schourup, Lawrence
2001 “Rethinking well .” Journal of Pragmatics 33 (7): 1025–1060. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Sperber, Dan, and Deirdre Wilson
1986Relevance: Communication and Cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
1995Relevance: Communication and Cognition. 2nd ed. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
1997 “The Mapping between the Mental and the Public Lexicon.” UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 9: 107–125.Google Scholar
1998 “The Mapping between the Mental and the Public Lexicon.” In Language and Thought: Interdisciplinary Themes, ed. by Peter Carruthers, and Jill Boucher, 184–200. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2008 “A Deflationary Account of Metaphors.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Metaphor and Thought, ed. by Raymond W. Gibbs, 84–105. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2012 “The Mapping between the Mental and the Public Lexicon.” In Meaning and Relevance, ed. by Deirdre Wilson, and Dan Sperber, 31–46. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2015 “Beyond Speaker’s Meaning.” Croatian Journal of Philosophy 15 (44): 117–149.Google Scholar
Światkowska, Marcela
2006 “L’interjection: Entre deixis et anaphore.” Langages 161 (1): 47–56. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Unger, Christoph
2019 “Allegory in Relation to Metaphor and Irony.” In Relevance: Pragmatics and Interpretation, ed. by Kate Scott, Robyn Carston, and Billy Clark, 240–252. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Vega Moreno, Rosa E.
2007Creativity and Convention: The Pragmatics of Everyday Figurative Speech. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Wałaszewska, Ewa
2010 “Simile in Relevance Theory: Towards an Alternative Account.” Acta Philologica 38: 13–19.Google Scholar
2011 “Broadening and Narrowing in Lexical Development: How Relevance Theory Can Account for Children’s Overextensions and Underextensions.” Journal of Pragmatics 43 (1): 314–326. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2020 “Category Extension as a Variety of Loose Use.” In Relevance Theory, Figuration, and Continuity in Pragmatics, ed. by Agnieszka Piskorska, 25–43. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Wearing, Catherine
2010 “Autism, Metaphor and Relevance Theory.” Mind & Language 25 (2): 196–216. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2014 “Interpreting Novel Metaphors.” International Review of Pragmatics 6 (1): 78–102. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Wharton, Tim
2001 “Natural Pragmatics and Natural Codes.” UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 13: 109–161.Google Scholar
2003 “Interjection, Language and the ‘Showing/Saying’ Continuum.” Pragmatics and Cognition 11 (1): 39–91. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2009Pragmatics and Non-Verbal Communication. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2012 “Pragmatics and Prosody.” In The Cambridge Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. by Keith Allan, and Kasia M. Jaszczolt, 567–584. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2016 “That Bloody So-and-so Has Retired: Expressives Revisited.” Lingua 175–176: 20–35. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Wierzbicka, Anna
1991Cross-Cultural Pragmatics: The Semantics of Human Interaction. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
1992 “The Semantics of Interjection.” Journal of Pragmatics 18 (2–3): 159–192. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Wilkins, David P.
1992 “Interjections and Deictics.” Journal of Pragmatics 18 (2–3): 119–158. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
1995 “Expanding the Traditional Category of Deictic Elements: Interjections as Deictics.” In Deixis in Narrative: A Cognitive Science Perspective, ed. by Judith F. Duchan, Gail A. Bruder, and Lynne E. Hewitt, 359–386. Hillsdale: LEA.Google Scholar
Wilson, Deirdre
2011a “The Conceptual–Procedural Distinction: Past, Present and Future.” In Procedural Meaning: Problems and Perspectives, ed. by Victoria Escandell-Vidal, Manuel Leonetti, and Aoife Ahern, 3–31. Bingley: Emerald Group Publishing. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2011b “Parallels and Differences in the Treatment of Metaphor in Relevance Theory and Cognitive Linguistics.” Intercultural Pragmatics 8 (2): 177–196. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2012 “Modality and the Conceptual–Procedural Distinction.” In Relevance Theory: More than Understanding, ed. by Ewa Wałaszewska, and Agnieszka Piskorska, 23–43. Newcastle: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.Google Scholar
Wilson, Deirdre, and Robyn Carston
2006 “Metaphor, Relevance and the ‘Emergent Property’ Issue.” Mind & Language 21 (3): 404–433. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2007 “A Unitary Approach to Lexical Pragmatics: Relevance, Inference and Ad Hoc Concepts.” In Pragmatics, ed. by Noel Burton-Roberts, 230–259. Basingstoke: Palgrave. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2019 “Pragmatics and the Challenge of ‘Non-Propositional’ Effects.” Journal of Pragmatics 145: 31–38. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Wilson, Deirdre, and Dan Sperber
2002 “Relevance Theory.” UCL Working Papers in Linguistics 14: 249–287.Google Scholar
2004 “Relevance Theory.” In The Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. by Larry Horn, and Gregory Ward, 607–632. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
2012Meaning and Relevance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Wilson, Deirdre, and Tim Wharton
2006 “Relevance and Prosody.” Journal of Pragmatics 38 (10): 1559–1579. DOI logoGoogle Scholar

Address for correspondence

Manuel Padilla Cruz

Departamento de Filología Inglesa (Lengua Inglesa)

Facultad de Filología

Universidad de Sevilla

c/ Palos de la Frontera, s/n.

41004 Sevilla

Spain

[email protected]

Biographical notes

Manuel Padilla Cruz (PhD) is an associate professor of English language and linguistics at Universidad de Sevilla. He teaches courses on pragmatics, discourse analysis, semantics and communication. His research interests fall within the field of pragmatics, where he has addressed a number of issues from a relevance-theoretic perspective. He has edited Relevance Theory. Recent Developments, Current Challenges and Future Directions (John Benjamins) and co-edited the special issue “New Developments in Relevance Theory” with Pragmatics & Cognition (John Benjamins).