References
Antony, L.M., & Levine, J
(1997) Reduction with autonomy. Noûs, 31(Suppl. 11), 83–105. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Baker, L.R
(1997) Why constitution is not identity. Journal of Philosophy, 94(12), 599–621. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(2000) Persons and bodies: A constitution view. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Bennett, K
(2004) Spatio-temporal coincidence and the grounding problem. Philosophical Studies, 118(3), 339–371. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(2011) Construction area (no hard hat required). Philosophical Studies, 154(1), 79–104. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Block, N
(1980) Introduction: What is functionalism? In N. Block (Ed.), Readings in Philosophy of Psychology, Vol. 1 (pp.171–184). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Block, N.J., & Fodor, J.A
(1972) What psychological states are not. Philosophical Review, 81(2), 159–181. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, D.J
(2000) What is a neural correlate of consciousness? In T. Metzinger (Ed.), Neural correlates of consciousness: Empirical and conceptual questions (pp.17–39). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Crick, F., & Koch, C
(1990) Toward a neurobiological theory of consciousness. Seminars in the Neurosciences, 2, 263–275. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(1995) Are we aware of neural activity in primary visual cortex? Nature, 375(6527), 121–123. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(1998) Consciousness and neuroscience. Cerebral Cortex, 8(2), 97–107. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Deutsch, H
(2008) Relative identity. In E.N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2008 edition). Retrieved from [URL]
Feigl, H
(1958) The “mental” and the “physical.” In H. Feigl, M. Scriven, & G. Maxwell (Eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 2: Concepts, theories, and the mind-body problem (pp.370–497). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Fine, K
(2008) Coincidence and form. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 82(1), 101–118. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J.A
(1997) Special sciences: Still autonomous after all these years. Noûs, 31(Suppl. 11), 149–163. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Funkhouser, E
(2006) The determinable-determinate relation. Noûs, 40(3), 548–569. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Gillett, C
(2002) The dimensions of realization: A critique of the standard view. Analysis, 62(4), 316–323. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Jackson, F
(2012) In defense of the identity theory mark I. In S. Gozzano & C.S. Hill (Eds.), New perspectives on type identity (pp.150–166). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Kim, J
(1998) Mind in a physical world: An essay on the mind-body problem and mental causation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Kim, J., & Sosa, E
(1999) Preface. In J. Kim & E. Sosa (Eds.), Metaphysics: An anthology (pp. ix–x). Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P
(1992) The naturalists return. Philosophical Review, 101(1), 53–114. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Kripke, S.A
(1980) Naming and necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Levine, J
(1983) Materialism and qualia: The explanatory gap. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64(4), 354–361.Google Scholar
Lewis, D
(Ed.) (1983) How to define theoretical terms. In Philosophical Papers, Vol. 1 (pp.78–96). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
(1999) Reduction of mind. In Papers in Metaphysics and Epistemology, Vol. 2 (pp.291–324). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Maddy, P
(2001) Naturalism: Friends and foes. Noûs, 35(Suppl. 15), 37–67. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
McLaughlin, B.P
(2010) Consciousness, type physicalism, and inference to the best explanation. Philosophical Issues, 20(1), 266–304. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Miller, S.M
(2001) Binocular rivalry and the cerebral hemispheres: With a note on the correlates and constitution of visual consciousness. Brain and Mind, 2(1), 119–149. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(2007) On the correlation/constitution distinction problem (and other hard problems) in the scientific study of consciousness. Acta Neuropsychiatrica, 19(3), 159–176. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(Ed.) (2013) The constitution of visual consciousness: Lessons from binocular rivalry. Advances in Consciousness Research (Vol. 90). Amsterdam, The Netherlands: John Benjamins Publishing Company. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Nagel, E
(1954) Naturalism reconsidered. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 28, 5–17. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Piccinini, G
(2004) Functionalism, computationalism, & mental states. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 35(4), 811–833. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(2010) The mind as neural software? Understanding functionalism, computationalism, and computational functionalism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81(2), 269–311. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Place, U.T
(1956) Is consciousness a brain process? British Journal of Psychology, 47(1), 44–50. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(1960) Materialism as a scientific hypothesis. Philosophical Review, 69(1), 101–104. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Polger, T.W
(2004) Natural minds. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
(2011) Are sensations still brain processes? Philosophical Psychology, 24(1), 1–21. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Pollen, D.A
(2011) On the emergence of primary visual perception. Cerebral Cortex, 21(9), 1941–1953. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H
(1967a) The mental life of some machines. In H.-N. Castaneda (Ed.), Intentionality, minds and perception. Detroit, MI: Wayne State University Press.Google Scholar
(1967b) Psychological predicates. In W.H. Capitan & D.D. Merrill (Eds.), Art, mind, and religion (pp.37–48). Pittsburgh, PA: Pittsburgh University Press.Google Scholar
(1973) Meaning and reference. The Journal of Philosophy, 70(19), 699–711. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Rees, G., Kreiman, G., & Koch, C
(2002) Neural correlates of consciousness in Humans. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 3(4), 261–270. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Ross, D., & Spurrett, D
(2004) What to say to a skeptical metaphysician? A defense manual for cognitive and behavioral scientists. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27(5), 603–627. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Salmon, W.C
(1989)  Four decades of scientific explanation (1st ed.). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
Searle, J.R
(1992) The rediscovery of the mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Shoemaker, S
(2001) Realization and mental causation. In C. Gillett & B. Loewer (Eds.), Physicalism and its discontents (pp.74–98). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(2003) Realization, micro-realization, and coincidence. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67(1), 1–23. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(2007) Physical realization. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Smart, J.J.C
(1959) Sensations and brain processes. Philosophical Review, 68(2), 141–156. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(2002) Sensations and brain processes. In D.J. Chalmers (Ed.), Philosophy of mind: Classical and contemporary readings (pp.60–68). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tong, F
(2005) Investigations of the neural basis of binocular rivalry. In D. Alais & R. Blake (Eds.), Binocular rivalry (pp.63–80). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Varzi, A
(2011) Mereology. In E.N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2011 edition). Retrieved from [URL]
Wasserman, R
(2014) Material constitution. In E.N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2014 edition). Retrieved from [URL]
Yablo, S
(1992) Mental causation. Philosophical Review, 101(2), 245–280. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Cited by

Cited by 1 other publications

Polák, Michal & Tomáš Marvan
2018. Neural Correlates of Consciousness Meet the Theory of Identity. Frontiers in Psychology 9 DOI logo

This list is based on CrossRef data as of 20 april 2024. Please note that it may not be complete. Sources presented here have been supplied by the respective publishers. Any errors therein should be reported to them.