Article In:
Cognitive Linguistic Studies
Vol. 12:1 (2025) ► pp.122
References (42)
References
Amsterdam, A. G., & Bruner, J. (2000). Minding the law. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Brandom, R. B. (1994). Making it explicit: Reasoning, representing, and discursive commitment. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Bruner, J. (2004). Life as narrative. Social Research, 71 (3), 691–710. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P. M. (1991). Folk psychology and the explanation of human behavior. In J. D. Greenwood (Ed.), The future of folk psychology (pp. 51–69). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Danto, A. C. (1965). Analytical philosophy of history. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dennett, D. C. (1971). Intentional systems. The Journal of Philosophy, 68 (4), 87–106. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(1991). Consciousness explained. Boston: Little Brown.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. A. (1975). The language of thought. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Gallagher, S. (2000). Philosophical conceptions of the self: Implications for cognitive science. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4 (1), 14–21. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(2006). The narrative alternative to theory of mind. In R. Menary (Ed.), Radical enactivism: Intentionality, phenomenology and narrative (pp. 223–229). Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(2013). The socially extended mind. Cognitive Systems Research, ( 25–26 ), 4–12. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Goldie, P. (2000). The emotions: A philosophical exploration. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
(2012). The mess inside: Narrative, emotion, and the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Herman, D. (2008). Narrative theory and the intentional stance. Partial Answers: Journal of Literature and the History of Ideas, 6 (2), 233–260. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Hutto, D. D. (2009). Folk psychology as narrative practice. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 16 (6–8), 9–39.Google Scholar
(2016). Narrative self-shaping: A modest proposal. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 15 1, 21–41. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(2022). A brickhouse defence for folk psychology: How to defeat “Big Bad Wolf” eliminativism. In T. Demeter, T. Parent & A. Toon (Eds.), Mental fictionalism: Philosophical explorations (pp. 160–183). London: Routledge. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Kerby, A. P. (1993). Narrative and the self. Indiana: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
Lakoff, G. (2008a). The political mind: A cognitive scientist’s guide to your brain and its politics. New York: Penguin.Google Scholar
(2008b). The neural theory of metaphor. In R. W. Gibbs, Jr. (Ed.), The Cambridge Handbook of Metaphor and Thought (pp. 17–38). New York: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1999). Philosophy in the flesh: The embodied mind and its challenge to western thought. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
MacIntyre, A. (1981). After virtue: A study in moral theory. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
McAdams, D. P. (2001). The psychology of life stories. Review of General Psychology, 5 (2), 100–122. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Menary, R. (2008). Embodied narratives. Journal of Counsciousness Studies, 15 (6), 63–84.Google Scholar
Meretoja, H. (2020). A dialogics of counter-narratives. In K. Lueg & M. W. Lundholt (Eds.), Routledge handbook of counter-narratives (pp. 30–42). London: Routledge. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Mink, L. O. (1981). Everyone his or her own annalist. In W. J. T. Mitchell (Ed.), On narrative (pp. 238–239). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Minsky, M. (1975). A framework for representing knowledge. In P. H. Winston (Ed.), The psychology of computer vision (pp. 211–277). New York: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
Ricoeur, P. (1991a). Life in quest of narrative. In D. Wood (Ed.), On paul ricoeur: Narrative and interpretation (pp. 20–33). London: Routledge. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(1991b). Narrative identity. In D. Wood (Ed.), On paul ricoeur: Narrative and interpretation (pp. 188–99). London: Routledge. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Rudd, A. (2012). Self, value, and narrative: A Kierkegaardian approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Scalise Sugiyama, M. (2008). Narrative as social mapping — case study: The trickster genre and free-rider problems. Ometeca, 12 1, 24–42.Google Scholar
Schechtman, M. (2007). Stories, lives, and basic survival: A refinement and defense of the narrative view. In Hutto, D. (Ed.). Narrative and understanding persons. Royal institute of philosophy supplement (pp. 155–178). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(2011). The narrative self. In S. Gallagher (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of the self (pp. 394–416). Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(2016). A mess indeed: Emphatic access, narrative, and identity. In J. Dodd (Ed.), Art, mind, and narrative: Themes from the work of Peter Goldie (pp.17–34). New York: Oxford University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Shank, R. C., & Abelson, R. P. (1977). Scripts, plans, goals and under standing. New York: Psychology Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Strawson, G. (2004). Against narrativity. Ratio, 17 (4), 428–452. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(2009). Selves: An essay in revisionary metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Tengelyi, L. (2012). Action and selfhood: A narrative interpretation. In D. Zahavi (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of contemporary phenomenology (pp. 265–287). Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Velleman, D. J. (2006). Self to self: Selected essays. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
White, H. (1973). Metahistory: The historical imagination in nineteenth-century Europe. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
(1999). Postmodernism and textual anxieties. In B. Strath & N. Witoszek (Eds.), The postmodern challenge: Perspectives east and west (pp. 27–45). London: Brill Rodopi.Google Scholar
Zahavi, D. (2007). Self and other: The limits of narrative understanding. In Hutto, D. (Ed.), Narrative and understanding persons. Royal institute of philosophy supplement (pp. 179–201). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar