Article published In:
Journal of Argumentation in Context
Vol. 4:3 (2015) ► pp.243285
References (58)
Albert, Hans. 1968. Traktat über kritische Vernunft. Tubingen: Mohr Siebeck. English Edition 1985. Treatise on Critical Reason. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Arras, John D. 1991, “Getting Down to Cases: The Revival of Casuistry in Bioethics.” The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 161: 29–51 DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Bakhtin, Mikhail M. 1929. Problemy tvorchestva Dostoevskogo. Leningrad: Priboĭ. Second Edition 1963. Problemy poetiki Dostoevskogo. Moskva: Sovetskiĭ pisatel. English Edition 1984. Problems of Dostoevsky’s Poetics. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Beauchamp, Tom L. 2003. “The Nature of Applied Ethics”. In A Companion to Applied Ethics, ed. by R.G. Frey and Christopher Heath Wellman, 1–16. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Bohman, James, and William Rehg. 2007. “Jürgen Habermas.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2011 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <[URL]>.Google Scholar
Boudon, Raymond. 1995. Le Juste et le Vrai. Études sur l’Objectivité des Valeurs et de la Connaissance. Paris: Fayard.Google Scholar
Chambers, Ted. 1999. The Fiction of Bioethics. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Clouser, K. Danner. 1993. “Bioethics and Philosophy”. Hasting Center Report 23 (6): S10–S11.Google Scholar
Eemeren, Frans H. van, and Rob Grootendorst. 1984. Speech Acts in Argumentative Discussions: A Theoretical Model for the Analysis of Discussions Directed towards Solving Conflicts of Opinion. Dordrecht/Berlin: Foris. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
. 1992. Argumentation, Communication and Fallacies. A Pragma-dialectical Perspective. Hillsdale (NJ): Lawrence Erlbaum.Google Scholar
. 2003a. A Systematic Theory Of Argumentation: The Pragma-dialectical Approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
. 2003b. “A Pragma-dialectical Procedure for a Critical Discussion.” Argumentation 171: 365–386. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Freeman, James B. 1991. Dialectics and the Macrostructure of Arguments; A Theory of Argument Structure. Berlin/New York: Foris. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Fries, Jacob Friedrich. 1807. Neue Oder Anthropologische Kritik der Vernunft (2nd edition). 1828–1831. Heidelberg: Winter.Google Scholar
Gilbert, Michael A. 1997. Coalescent Argumentation, New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Guevara, Daniel. 2008. “Rebutting Formally Valid Counterexamples to the Humean “Is-Ought” Dictum”. Synthese 1641: 45–60. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen. 1981. Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns. Vol. 1: Handlungsrationalität und gesellschaftliche Rationalisierung. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. English edition 1984. The Theory of Communicative Action: Vol. I, Reason and the Rationalization of Society. Boston: Beacon Press.Google Scholar
. 1983. Moralbewußtsein und kommunikatives Handeln. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. English edition 1990. Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
. 1990. Die nachholende Revolution. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. English Translation in Habermas 1993.Google Scholar
. 1991a. Erläuterungen zur Diskursethik. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. English Translation in Habermas 1993.Google Scholar
. 1991b. “Einen unbedingten Sinn zu retten ohne Gott, ist eitel: Reflexionen über einen Satz von Max Horkheimer.” In Kritischer Materialismus, ed. by M. Lutz-Bachmann and G. Schmid Noerr. München: Karl Hanser. English Translation in Habermas 1993.Google Scholar
. 1992. Faktizität und Geltung. Beiträge zur Diskurstheorie des Rechtes und des demokratischen Rechtsstaats. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. English edition 1996. Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
. 1993. Justification and Application. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
. 1998. On the Pragmatics of Communication. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
. 2001. Die Zukunft der menschlichen Natur. Auf dem Weg zu einer liberalen Eugenik? Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. English edition 2003. The Future of Human Nature. Cambridge: Polity.Google Scholar
Hare, H.R. 1952. The Language of Morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hempel, Carl G. 1962. “Deductive-Nomological vs. Statistical Explanation.” In Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science III, ed. by Herbert Feigl and Grover Maxwell. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Hempel, Carl G., and Paul Oppenheim. 1948. “Studies in the Logic of Explanation.” Philosophy of Science 151: 135–175. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Hill, Scott. 2009. “Good News for the Logical Autonomy of Ethics.” Argumentation 231: 277–283. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Horgan, Terence, and Mark Timmons. 1991. “New Wave Moral Realism Meets Moral Twin Earth.” Journal of Philosophical Research 161: 447–465. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
. 1992a. “Troubles on Moral Twin Earth: Moral Queerness Revived.” Synthese 921: 221–260. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
. 1992b. “Troubles for New Wave Moral Semantics: The Open Question Argument Revived.” Philosophical Papers 211: 153–172. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Jensen, Albert, and Stephen Toulmin. 1988. The Abuse of Casuistry: A History of Moral Reasoning. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Joyce, Richard. 2009. “Moral Anti-Realism”. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2009 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <[URL]>.Google Scholar
Karmo, Toomas. 1988. “Some Valid (but not Sound) Arguments Trivially Span the “Is”-“Ought” Gap”. Mind 971: 252–257. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Mackie, J.L. 1977. Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong. London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Marks, Joel. 1988. “When Is a Fallacy not a Fallacy?Metaphilosophy 191: 307–312. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Moore, G.E. 1903. Principia Ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nelson, Mark T. 1995. “Is It Always Fallacious to Derive Values from Facts?Argumentation 91: 553–562. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
. 2003. “Who Needs Valid Moral Arguments?Argumentation 171: 35–42. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
. 2007. “More Bad News for the Logical Autonomy of Ethics.” Canadian Journal of Philosophy 371: 203–216. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Perelman, Chaïm. 1961. “Jugements de Valeur, Justification et Argumentation”. Revue International de Philosophie 58 (4): 325–335.Google Scholar
Perelman, Chaïm, and Lucie Olbrechts-Tyteca. 1958. Traité de L’Argumentation. La Nouvelle Rhétorique. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. English Edition 1969. The New Rhetoric: A Treatise on Argumentation. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Peters, R.S. 1966. Ethics and Education. London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd.Google Scholar
Pidgen, Charles R. 1989. “Logic and the Autonomy of Ethics”. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 671: 127–151. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
. 1991. “Naturalism”. In A Companion to Ethics, ed. by Peter Singer, 421–431. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. 1934. Logik der Forschung. Wien: Julius Springler Verlag. English edition 1959. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar
Prinz, Jesse J. 2007. The Emotional Construction of Morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van Orman, and J.S. Ullian. 1970. The Web of Belief. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Rescher, Nicholas. 1962. “The Stochastic Revolution and the Nature of Scientific Explanation.” Synthese 141: 200–215. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Salmon, Wesley C. 1989. Four Decades of Scientific Explanation. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Schurz, Gerhard. 1997. The Is-Ought Problem: An Investigation In Philosophical Logic. Dordrecht: Kluwer. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Thomson, Judith Jarvis. 1971. “A Defense of Abortion.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 1 (1): 47–66.Google Scholar
Toulmin, Stephen. 1950. An Examination of the Place of Reason in Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
. 1982. “How Medicine Saved the Life of Ethics.” Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 251: 736–750. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Walton, Douglas. 1996. Argumentation Schemes for Presumptive Reasoning. Mahwah (New Jersey): Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
. 2003. Ethical Argumentation. Lanham (Maryland): Lexington Books.Google Scholar
. 2007. Dialog Theory for Critical Argumentation. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Cited by (1)

Cited by one other publication

Bacchini, Fabio
2016. Epistemology and Responsibility. Corela :HS-19 DOI logo

This list is based on CrossRef data as of 4 july 2024. Please note that it may not be complete. Sources presented here have been supplied by the respective publishers. Any errors therein should be reported to them.