Article published In:
Pragmatics & Cognition
Vol. 26:2/3 (2019) ► pp.239266
References (66)
References
Allopenna, Paul D., James S. Magnuson & Michael K. Tanenhaus. 1998. Tracking the time course of spoken word recognition using eye movements: Evidence for continuous mapping models. Journal of Memory and Language. 38(4). 419–439. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Altmann, Gerry T. M. & Jelena Mirković. 2009. Incrementality and prediction in human sentence processing. Cognitive Science 33(4). 583–609. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Azzouni, Jody. 2013. Semantic perception: How the illusion of a common language arises and persists. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Barsalou, Lawrence W. 2009. Simulation, situated conceptualization, and prediction. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 364(1521). 1281–1289. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
2011. Integrating Bayesian analysis and mechanistic theories in grounded cognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 34(04). 191–192. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Barsalou, Lawrence W., Ava Santos, W. Kyle Simmons & Christine D. Wilson. 2008. Language and simulation in conceptual processing. In Manuel de Vega, Arthur Glenberg & Arthur Graesser (eds.), Symbols and embodiment: Debates on meaning and cognition, 245–283. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Barton, Stephen B. & Anthony J. Sanford. 1993. A case study of anomaly detection: Shallow semantic processing and cohesion establishment. Memory & Cognition 21(4). 477–487. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Barwise, Jon & John Etchemendy. 1987. The liar: An essay on truth and circularity. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bašnáková, Jana, Kirsten Weber, Karl M. Petersson, Jos van Berkum & Peter Hagoort. 2014. Beyond the language given: The neural correlates of inferring speaker meaning. Cerebral Cortex. 24(10). 2572–2578. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Beall, Jc, Michael Glanzberg & David Ripley. 2019. “Liar Paradox”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2019 Edition). Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <[URL]>. (12 March, 2020).
Berkum, Jos J. van, Danielle Van den Brink, Cathelijne M. Tesink, Miriam Kos & Peter Hagoort. 2008. The neural integration of speaker and message. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience. 20(4). 580–591. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Camp, Elisabeth. 2004. The generality constraint and categorial restrictions. The Philosophical Quarterly, 54(215). 209–231. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Carston, Robin. 2002. Thoughts and Utterances. Oxford: Blackwell. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Casasanto, Daniel & Gary Lupyan. 2015. All concepts are ad hoc concepts. In Eric Margolis & Stephen Laurence (eds.), The conceptual mind: New directions in the study of concepts, 543–566. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Chomsky, Noam. 2002. Syntactic structures, 2nd edn. Berlin & New York: Mouton de Gruyter. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Clark, Andy. 1998. Magic words: How language augments human computation. In Peter Carruthers & Jill Boucher (eds.), Language and thought: Interdisciplinary themes, 162–183. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
. 2013. Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36(03). 181–204. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
. 2016. Surfing uncertainty: Prediction, action, and the embodied mind. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Dam, Wessel O. van, Margriet van Dijk, Harold Bekkering & Shirley-Ann Rueschemeyer. 2012. Flexibility in embodied lexical-semantic representations. Human Brain Mapping 33(10). 2322–2333. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Dam, Wessel O. van, Eelco V. van Dongen, Harold Bekkering & Shirley-Ann Rueschemeyer. 2012. Context-dependent changes in functional connectivity of auditory cortices during the perception of object words. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 24(10). 2108–2119. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Davidson, Donald. 1986. A nice derangement of epitaphs. In Ernest Lepore (ed.), Truth and interpretation: Perspectives on the philosophy of Donald Davidson, 433–446. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Dell, Gary S. & Franklin Chang. 2013. The P-chain: Relating sentence production and its disorders to comprehension and acquisition. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 369(1634). DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Dutilh Novaes, Catarina. 2012. Formal languages in logic: A philosophical and cognitive analysis. Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Elqayam, Shira. 2006. The collapse illusion effect: A semantic-pragmatic illusion of truth and paradox. Thinking & Reasoning 12(2). 144–180. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Erickson, Thomas D. & Mark E. Mattson. 1981. From words to meaning: A semantic illusion. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior 20(5), 540–551. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Escher, Maurits C. 1971. The graphic work of M. C. Escher. New York: Ballantine.Google Scholar
Evans, Gareth & John H. McDowell. 1982. The varieties of reference. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, Jerry A. 1979. The language of thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, Jerry A. & Zenon W. Pylyshyn. 2015. Minds without meanings: An essay on the content of concepts. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fraassen, Bas van. 1970. Truth and Paradoxical Consequences. In Robert Martin (ed.), The paradox of the liar, 13–23. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Friston, Karl. 2010. The free-energy principle: A unified brain theory? Nature Reviews Neuroscience. 11(2). 127–138. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Gagnepain, Pierre, Richard N. Henson & Matthew H. Davis. 2012. Temporal Predictive Codes for Spoken Words in Auditory Cortex. Current Biology 22(7). 615–621. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Gerstenberg, Tobias & Joshua B. Tenenbaum. 2017. Intuitive theories. In Michael R. Waldmann (ed.), Oxford Handbook of Causal Reasoning, 515–548. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Goldstein, Laurence. 1981. Categories of linguistic aspects and Grelling’s paradox. Linguistics and Philosophy. 4(3). 405–421. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
. 1982. Linguistic aspects, meaninglessness and paradox: A rejoinder to John David Stone. Linguistics and Philosophy 4(4). 579–592. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Hagoort, Peter & Jos van Berkum. 2007. Beyond the sentence given. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 362(1481), 801–811. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Hoenig, Klaus, Eun-Jin Sim, Victor Bochev, Bärbel Herrnberger & Markus Kiefer. 2008. Conceptual flexibility in the human brain: Dynamic recruitment of semantic maps from visual, motor, and motion-related areas. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 20(10). 1799–1814. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Hohwy, Jacob. 2013. The predictive mind. Oxford, UK, New York, NY: Oxford University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Kearns, John T. 2007. An illocutionary logical explanation of the liar paradox. History and Philosophy of Logic. 28(1). 31–66. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Kripke, Saul. 1975. Outline of a theory of truth. The Journal of Philosophy 72(19). 690–716. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Kuperberg, Gina R. & Tim F. Jaeger. 2016. What do we mean by prediction in language comprehension? Language, Cognition and Neuroscience 31(1). 32–59. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Kutas, Marta, Katherine A. DeLong & Nathaniel J. Smith. 2011. A look around at what lies ahead: Prediction and predictability in language processing. In Moshe Bar (ed.), Predictions in the brain: Using our past to generate a future, 190–207. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Lakoff, George & Rafael E. Núñez. 2000. Where mathematics comes from: How the embodied mind brings mathematics into being, 1st edn. New York, NY: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Langacker, Ronald W. 2008. Cognitive grammar: A basic introduction. Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Leitgeb, Hannes. 2007. What theories of truth should be like (but cannot be). Philosophy Compass 2(2). 276–290. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Ludlow, Peter. 2014. Living words: Meaning underdetermination and the dynamic lexicon, 1st edn. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Lupyan, Gary & Andy Clark. 2015. Words and the world: Predictive coding and the language-perception-cognition interface. Current Directions in Psychological Science 24(4). 279–284. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Magidor, Ofra. 2013. Category mistakes. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Martinich, Aloysius. P. 1983. A pragmatic solution to the Liar Paradox. Philosophical Studies 43(1). 63–67. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Michel, Christian. 2020. Concept contextualism through the lens of predictive processing. Philosophical Psychology. 33(4). 624–647. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Paivio, Allan. 1990. Mental representations: A dual coding approach. Cary: Oxford University Press. Retrieved from [URL]. (12 March, 2020). DOI logo
Peacocke, Christopher. 1992. A study of concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Penrose, Lionel S. & Roger Penrose. 1958. Impossible objects: A special type of visual illusion. British Journal of Psychology 49(1). 31–33. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Pickering, Martin J. & Simon Garrod. 2013. An integrated theory of language production and comprehension. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36(04). 329–347. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Priest, Graham. 1984. Logic of paradox revisited. Journal of Philosophical Logic 13(2). 153–179. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
. 2006. In contradiction: A study of the transconsistent. Oxford: Clarendon Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Rayo, Agustin. 2013. A plea for semantic localism. Noûs 47(4). 647–679. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Rice, Collin. 2016. Concepts as Pluralistic Hybrids. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 92(3). 597–619. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Ripley, David. 2016. Experimental philosophical logic. In Justin Sytsma (ed.), A companion to experimental philosophy, 523–534. Wesley Buckwalter.Google Scholar
Rips, Lance J. 1989. The Psychology of Knights and Knaves. Cognition 31(2). 85–116. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Schroeder, Severin. 2004. Why Juliet is the Sun. In Mark Siebel and Mark Textor (eds.), Semantic and ontology, 63–100. Frankfurt a.M: Ontos Verlag. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Simmons, W. Kyle, Stephan B. Hamann, Carla L. Harenski, Xiaoping P. Hu & Lawrence W. Barsalou. 2008. fMRI evidence for word association and situated simulation in conceptual processing. Journal of Physiology-Paris 102(1–3). 106–119. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Strawson, Peter F. 1959. Individuals: An essay in descriptive metaphysics. London: Methuen & Co. Ltd.Google Scholar
Tversky, Amos, & Daniel Kahneman. 1974. Judgment under Uncertainty: Heuristics and Biases. Science 185(4157). 1124–1131. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Williamson, Timothy. 1996. Vagueness. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Yablo, Steven. 1985. Truth and reflection, Journal of Philosophical Logic 141. 297–349. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Cited by (4)

Cited by four other publications

Michel, Christian
2023. Scaling up Predictive Processing to language with Construction Grammar. Philosophical Psychology 36:3  pp. 553 ff. DOI logo
Michel, Christian
2023. Towards a new standard model of concepts?. Philosophical Psychology  pp. 1 ff. DOI logo
Vicente, Agustín, Christian Michel & Valentina Petrolini
2023. Literalism in Autistic People: a Predictive Processing Proposal. Review of Philosophy and Psychology DOI logo
LÖHR, GUIDO & CHRISTIAN MICHEL
2022. PREDICTIVE PROCESSING AND THE SEMIOLOGICAL PRINCIPLE: COMMENTARY TO DUFFLEY. Manuscrito 45:1  pp. 5 ff. DOI logo

This list is based on CrossRef data as of 21 september 2024. Please note that it may not be complete. Sources presented here have been supplied by the respective publishers. Any errors therein should be reported to them.