Article published In:
New Developments in Relevance Theory
Edited by Manuel Padilla Cruz and Agnieszka Piskorska
[Pragmatics & Cognition 28:2] 2021
► pp. 416440
References (51)
References
Austin, John L. 1962. How to do things with words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Bach, Emmon. 1989. Informal lectures on formal semantics. New York: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Beaver, David. 2021. Two minutes hate. Plenary lecture delivered at the 17th International Pragmatics Conference. Winterthur: 2 July 2021.
Beaver, David & Jason Stanley. Forthcoming. Hustle: The politics of language. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Blackburn, Simon. 2017. Truth. London: Profile Books.Google Scholar
Carston, Robyn. 2002. Utterances and thought: The pragmatics of explicit communication. Oxford: Blackwell. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Changeux, Jean-Pierre. 2002. L’homme de vérité. Paris: Odile Jacob.Google Scholar
. 2004. The physiology of truth: Neuroscience and human knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University press.Google Scholar
Cohen, L. Jonathan. 1971. Some remarks on Grice’s view about the logical particles of natural language. In Yehoshua Bar-Hillel (ed.), Pragmatics of natural language, 50–68. Dordrecht: Reidel. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Dowty, David, Robert E. Wall & Stanley Peters. 1981. Introduction to Montague semantics. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Fauconnier, Gilles. 1985. Mental spaces: Aspects of meaning construction in natural language. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, Harry G. 2005. On bullshit. Oxford: Princeton University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Frege, Gottlob. [1892]1948. Sense and reference. The Philosophical Review 57 (3). 209–230. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Gazdar, Gerald. 1979. Pragmatics: Implicature, presupposition, and logical form. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Green, Mitchell S. & John N. Williams (eds). 2007. Moore’s paradox: New essays on belief, rationality, and the first person. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Grice, H. Paul. 1975. Logic and conversation. In Peter Cole & Jerry L. Morgan (eds.), Syntax and semantics 3: Speech acts, 40–58. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Gygax, Pascal, Sandrine Zufferey & Ute Gabriel. 2021. Le cerveau pense-t-il au masculin? Cerveau, langage et représentations sexistes. Paris: Le Robert.Google Scholar
Karttunen, Lauri & Stanley Peters. 1979. Conventional implicature. In Choon-Kyu Oh & David A. Dinneen (eds.), Syntax and semantics 11: Presupposition, 1–56. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Kecskes, Istvan. Forthcoming. The interplay of linguistic, conceptual and encyclopedic knowledge in meaning construction and comprehension. In Jesus Romero-Trillo (ed.), The handbook of language and context. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Lakoff, George. 1987. Women, fire and dangerous things: What categories reveal about the mind. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Levinson, Stephen C. 2000. Presumptive meanings: The theory of generalized conversational implicature. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
McConnell-Ginet, Sally. 2020. Words matter: Language and power. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
McIntyre, Lee. 2018. Post-truth. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Mercier, Hugo. 2020. Not born yesterday: The science of who we trust and what we believe. Oxford: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Mercier, Hugo & Dan Sperber. 2017. The enigma of reason: A new theory of human understanding. London: Allen Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Moeschler, Jacques. 2019. Non-lexical pragmatics: Time, causality and logical words. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
. 2021. Why language? What pragmatics tells us about language and communication. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
. Forthcoming. The role of context in Gricean and neo-Gricean pragmatics. In Jesus Romero-Trillo (ed.), The Cambridge handbook of language and context. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Moore, George E. 1993. Moore’s paradox. In Thomas Baldwin (ed.), G. E. Moore: Selected writings, 207–212. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Origgi, Gloria. 2015. La réputation: Qui dit quoi à qui. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Ortony, Andrew. 1979. Metaphor: A multidimensional problem. In Andrew Ortony (ed.), 1–16. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Pinker, Steven, Martin A. Novak & James L. Lee. 2008. The logic of indirect speech. PNAS 105(3). 833–838. [URL] cgi pnas.0707192105. DOI logo
Reboul, Anne. 1992. Le paradoxe du mensonge dans la théorie des actes de langage. Cahiers de Linguistique Française 131. 125–147.Google Scholar
. 2013. The social evolution of language and the necessity of implicit communication. In Stephen R. Anderson, Jacques Moeschler & Fabienne Reboul (eds.), The language-cognition interface, 253–273. Geneva: Droz.Google Scholar
. 2017. Cognition and communication in the evolution of language. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Recanati, François. 2010. Truth-conditional pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Reid, Thomas. [1764]1970. Inquiry into the human mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Roberts, Craige. 2004. Context in dynamic interpretation. In Laurence R. Horn & Gregory Ward (eds.), The handbook of pragmatics, 197–220. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Sadock, Jerrold M. 1978. On testing for conversational implicature. In Peter Cole (ed.), Syntax and semantics 9: Pragmatics, 281–297. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Searle, John R. 1969. Speech acts: An essay in the philosophy of language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
1979. Expression and meaning: Studies in the theory of speech acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Sperber, Dan. 1996. Explaining Culture: A Naturalistic Approach. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Sperber, Dan & Deirdre Wilson. 1995. Relevance: Communication and cognition. Oxford: Blackwell, 2nd ed.Google Scholar
Sperber, Dan, Fabrice Clément, Christophe Heintz, Olivier Mascaro, Hugo Mercier, Gloria Origgi & Deirdre Wilson. 2010. Epistemic vigilance. Mind & Language 25 (4). 359–393. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Stalnaker, Ronald C. 1977. Pragmatic presuppositions. In Andy Rogers, Bob Wall & John P. Murphy (eds.), Proceedings of the Texas conference on performatives, presuppositions and implicatures, 135–147. Arlington: Center for Applied Linguistics. Reprinted in Stalnaker 1999.Google Scholar
Stanley, Jason. 2018. How fascism works: The politics of us and them. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
Wilson, Deirdre. 2017. Irony, hyperbole, jokes and banter. In Joanna Blochowiak, Cristina Grisot, Stephanie Durrleman & Christopher Laenzlinger (eds.), Formal models in the study of language: Applications in interdisciplinary contexts, 201–219. Cham: Springer. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Wilson, Deirdre & Robyn Carston. 2007. A unitary approach to lexical pragmatics: Relevance, inference and ad hoc concepts. In Noel Burton-Roberts (ed.), Pragmatics, 230–259. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Wilson, Deirdre & Dan Sperber. 2004. Relevance Theory. In Laurence R. Horn and Gregory Ward (eds.), The handbook of pragmatics, 607–632. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
. 2012. Truthfulness and relevance. In Meaning and relevance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Zufferey, Sandrine, Jacques Moeschler & Anne Reboul. 2019. Implicatures. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Cited by (2)

Cited by two other publications

Allan, Keith
2023. Why truth is necessarily pragmatic. Intercultural Pragmatics 20:3  pp. 251 ff. DOI logo
Moeschler, Jacques
2023. What makes inferences reliable? The unpredictable relationship between pragmatic inference and truth. Journal of Pragmatics 218  pp. 153 ff. DOI logo

This list is based on CrossRef data as of 5 july 2024. Please note that it may not be complete. Sources presented here have been supplied by the respective publishers. Any errors therein should be reported to them.