Article published In:
Pragmatics & Cognition
Vol. 27:2 (2020) ► pp.387407
References (51)
References
Allwood, Jens. 1981. On the distinctions between semantics and pragmatics. In Wolfgang Klein & Willem Levelt (eds.), Crossing the boundaries in linguistics, 177–189. Dordrecht: Springer. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Atkin, Albert. 2005. Peirce on the index and indexical reference. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 61(1), 161–188.Google Scholar
Bach, Kent. 2004. Pragmatics and the philosophy of language. In Laurence R. Horn & Gregory Ward (eds). The handbook of pragmatics, 463–487. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Bar-Hillel, Yehoshua. 1954. Indexical expressions. Mind, New Series, 63(251). 359–379. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Bergman, Mats. 2009. Peirce’s philosophy of communication: The rhetorical underpinnings of the theory of signs. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
Brandom, Robert. 1994. Making it explicit. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
. 2008. Between saying and doing: Towards an analytic pragmatism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Braun, David. 2015. Indexicals. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. [URL] (Downloaded June 9, 2019).
Brown, Roger. 1958. How shall a thing be called? Psychological Review 65(1). 14–21. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Castañeda, Hector-Neri. 1989. Direct reference, the semantics of thinking, and guise theory. In James Almog, John Perry & Howard Wettstein (eds.), Themes from Kaplan, 105–144. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Champagne, Marc. 2015. A less simplistic metaphysics: Peirce’s layered theory of meaning as a layered theory of being. Sign Systems Studies 43(4). 523–559. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
. 2019. ______ is necessary for interpreting a proposition. Chinese Semiotic Studies 15(1). 39–48. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Davidson, Donald. 1967. Truth and meaning. Synthese 17(1). 304–323. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Davies, Martin & Lloyd Humberstone. 1980. Two notions of necessity. Philosophical Studies 38(1). 1–30. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Fotion, Nick. 1995. Pragmatics. In Ted Honderich (ed.), The Oxford companion to philosophy, 23–43. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Gazdar, Gerald. 1979. Pragmatics: Implicature, presupposition, and logical form. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Gendler-Szabó, Zoltan. 2005. Semantics versus pragmatics. Oxford: OUP. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Goudge, Thomas. 1965. Peirce’s index. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 1(2). 52–70.Google Scholar
Horn, Laurence R. & Gregory Ward (eds.). 2004. The handbook of pragmatics. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Houser, Nathan. 2020. Semiotics and philosophy. The American Journal of Semiotics, forthcoming. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Husserl, Edmund. 1913. Logical investigations, trans. J. N. Findlay. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Kaplan, David. 1989. Demonstratives: An essay on the semantics, logic, metaphysics and epistemology of demonstratives. In James Almog, John Perry & Howard Wettstein (eds.), Themes from Kaplan, 481–565. Oxford: OUP.Google Scholar
Katz, Jerrold. 1977. Propositional structure and illocutionary force: A study of the contribution of sentence meaning to speech acts. New York: Crowell.Google Scholar
Kempson, Ruth. 1988. Grammar and conversational principles. In Frederick Newmeyer (ed.), Linguistics: The Cambridge survey, vol. 21, 139–163. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Korta, Kepa & John Perry. 2015. Pragmatics. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. [URL] (Downloaded June 7, 2019).
Kukla, Rebecca & Mark N. Lance. 2009. ‘Yo!’ and ‘lo!’: The pragmatic topography of the space of reasons. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lefebvre, Martin. 2007. The art of pointing. On Peirce, indexicality, and photographic images. In James Elkins (ed.), Photography theory, 220–244. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
. 2010. De quelques airs de famille: Remarques sur le langage et la ressemblance chez Peirce et Wittgenstein. In Francois Latraverse (ed.), Peirce, Wittgenstein et le pragmatism, 1–22. Paris: L’Harmattan.Google Scholar
Legg, Catherine. 2008. The problem of the essential icon. American Philosophical Quarterly 45(3). 207–232.Google Scholar
. 2014. Charles Peirce’s limit concept of truth. Philosophy Compass 9(3). 204–213. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Levine, Steven. 2010. Rehabilitating objectivity: Rorty, Brandom, and the New Pragmatism. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 40(4). 567–589. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Millikan, Ruth Garrett. 1990. The myth of the essential indexical. Noûs 241. 723–734. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Morris, Charles. 1938. Foundations of the theory of signs. In Otto Neurath, Rudolf Carnap & Charles Morris (eds.), International encyclopedia of unified science I, 77–138. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Peirce, Charles S. 1885. On the algebra of logic: A contribution to the philosophy of notation. American Journal of Mathematics 7(2–3). 180–196. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Peirce, Charles S. 1992. Essential Peirce, vol. 1: Selected philosophical writings (1867–1893). Eds. Nathan Houser & Christian Kloesel. Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
1998. Essential Peirce, vol. 2: Selected philosophical writings (1893–1913). Eds. Nathan Houser & Christian Kloesel. Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
1931–58. Collected papers (vol. 1–8). Eds. Charles Hartshorne, Paul Weiss & Arthur Burks. Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Perry, John. 1979. The problem of the essential indexical. Noûs 131. 3–21. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
. 1997. Indexicals and demonstratives. In Bob Hale & Crispin Wright (eds.), Companion to the philosophy of language, 586–612. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
. 1998. Indexicals, contexts and unarticulated constituents. In Proceedings of the 1995 CSLI-Amsterdam logic, language and computation conference. Stanford: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard V. O. 1960. Word and object. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Recanati, Francois. 2001. What is said. Synthese 128(1–2). 75–91. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
. 2012. Pragmatic enrichment. In Gillian Russell & Delia Graff Fara (eds.), Routledge companion to the philosophy of language, 67–78. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Reichenbach, Hans. 1947. Elements of symbolic logic. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Rommetveit, Ragnar. 1988. On literacy and the myth of literal meaning. In Roger Säljö (ed.), The written world: Studies in literate thought and action, 13–40. Berlin: Springer. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Russell, Bertrand. 1948. Human knowledge: Its scope and its limits. London: Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, Robert. 1970. Pragmatics. Synthese 22(1–2). 272–289. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Swindal, James. 2007. Can a discursive pragmatism guarantee objectivity? Habermas and Brandom on the correctness of norms. Philosophy and Social Criticism 33(1). 113–126. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Tarski, Alfred. 1983. The concept of truth in the languages of the deductive sciences. In Joseph Henry Woodger (trs.), Logic, semantics, metamathematics: Papers from 1923 to 1938, 156–278. Hackett: Indianapolis.Google Scholar
Voss, Stephen & Charles Sayward. 1976. Eternal sentences. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 54(1). 14–23. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Wettstein, Howard. 1986. Has semantics rested on a mistake? The Journal of Philosophy 83(4). 185–209. DOI logoGoogle Scholar