References

Bibliography

Ackermann, Wilhelm
(1950): “Widerspruchsfreier Aufbau der Logik, I.” The Journal of Symbolic Logic 15: 33–57. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(1953): “Widerspruchsfreier Aufbau einer typenfreien Logik, II.” Mathematische Zeitschrift 57: 155–166. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(1965): “Der Aufbau einer höheren Logik.” Archiv für mathematische Logik und Grundlagenforschung 7: 5–22. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Anderson, Alan Ross & Belnap, Nuel D
(1975): The Logic of Relevance and Necessity . Vol. 1. Princeton and London: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Anderson, C. Anthony
(1984): “General intensional logic.” In: Dov Gabbay & Franz Guenthner (eds.) The Handbook of Philosophical Logic , Vol. II, Dordrecht: Reidel. 355–385. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Bacon, John
(1973): “Do generic description denote?” Mind 82: 331–347. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Bealer, George
(1982): Quality and Concept . Oxford: Clarendon Press. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Boolos, George
(1998a): “The iterative conception of set.” In: Boolos(1998b: p 13–29). Originally published in The Journal of Philosophy 68 (1971). 215–232.Google Scholar
(1998b): Logic, Logic, and Logic . Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Cantor, Georg
(1890/91): “Über eine elementare Frage der Mannigfaltigkeitslehre.” Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung 1: 75–78. Reprinted: Cantor (1932: p. 278–281).Google Scholar
(1895): “Beiträge zur Begründung der transfiniten Mengenlehre.” Mathematische Annalen 46: 481–512. Reprinted (together with the continuation of this article): Cantor (1932: p. 282–351). DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(1932): Abhandlungen mathematischen und philosophischen Inhalts . Edited by Ernst Zermelo. Berlin: Springer. Reprinted: Hildesheim and New York: Olms 1966.Google Scholar
Carpenter, Robert L
(1997): Type-logical Semantics . Cambridge MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Chierchia, Gennaro
(1982): “Nominalization and Montague grammar: A semantics without types for natural languages.” Linguistics and Philosophy 5: 303–354. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(1988): Topics in the Syntax and Semantics of Infinitives and Gerunds . New York and London: Garland.Google Scholar
Cocchiarella, Nino B
(1987): Logical Studies in Early Analytic Philosophy . Columbus OH: Ohio State University Press.Google Scholar
Cochiarella, Nino B
(1986): Logical Investigations of Predication Theory and the Problem of Universals . Naples: Bibliopolis.Google Scholar
Cooper, William S
(1978): Foundations of Logico-Linguistics . Dordrecht: Reidel. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Curry, Haskel B
(1942): “The inconsistency of certain formal logics.” The Journal of Symbolic Logic 7: 115–117. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Curry, Haskell B
(1963): Foundations of Mathematical Logic . New York etc.: MacGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
Curry, Haskell B. & Feys, Robert
(1958): Combinatory Logic . Vol. 1. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Dummett, Michael
(1973): Frege. Philosophy of Language . London: Duckworth. 2nd edition 1981.Google Scholar
Feferman, Solomon
(1975): “Non-extensional type-free theories of partial operaions and classifications, I.” In: Justus Diller & Gert Heinz Müller (eds.) |= ISILC Proof Theory Symposium. Dedicated to Kurt Schütte on the Occasion of His 65th Birthday ,Berlin, Heidelberg, and New York: Springer. 73–118.Google Scholar
(1984): “Toward useful type-free theories, I.” In: Robert L. Martin (ed.) Recent Essays on Truth and the Liar Paradox , Oxford:Clarendon Press.237–306. Also in: The Journal of Symbolic Logic . 49 (1984). 75–111.Google Scholar
Fine, Kit
(2002): The Limits of Abstraction . Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Frege, Gottlob
(1884): Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik. Eine logisch-mathematische Untersuchung über den Begriff der Zahl . Breslau: Koebner. Centenary edition. Hamburg: Meiner1986.Google Scholar
(1892): “Über Begriff und Gegenstand.” Vierteljahresschrift für wissenschaftliche Philosophie 16: 192–205. Reprinted: Frege (1990: p. 167–178).Google Scholar
(1893/1903): Grundgesetze der Arithmetik . 2 Vols. Jena: Pohle. Reprinted: Hildesheim and New York: Olms 1966.Google Scholar
(1918/19): “Der Gedanke.” Beiträge zur Philosophie des deutschen Idealismus 1: 58–77. Reprinted: Frege (1990: p. 342–362). English translation: “The thought: A Logical Inquiry”. Mind 65 (1956). 289–311.Google Scholar
(1990): Kleine Schriften . Edited by Ignacio Angelelli. Hildesheim and New York: Olms, 2nd edition. 1st edition 1967.Google Scholar
Geach, Peter
(1950): “Subject and predicate.” Mind 59: 127–162.Google Scholar
(1962): Reference and Generality. An Examination of Some Medieval and Modern Theories . Ithaca NY and London: Cornell University Press. 3rd edition 1980.Google Scholar
(1967): “Identity.” Review of Metaphysics 21. Reprinted: Geach, Thomas: Logic Matters. Oxford: Blackwell 1972. 2nd, corrected edition 1981. p. 238–247.Google Scholar
Groenendijk, Jeroen & Stokhof, Martin
(1984): “Studies in the semantics of questions and the pragmatics of answers.” Ph.D. thesis, University of Amsterdam.Google Scholar
Grover, Dorothy L., Camp, Joseph L. & Belnap, Nuel D
(1974): “A prosentential theory of truth.” Philosophical Studies 27: 73–125. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Gupta, Anil
(1980): The Logic of Common Nouns. An Investigation in Quantified Modal Logic . New Haven and London: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Hale, Bob
(2001): “Singular terms (1), (2).” In: Hale & Wright (2001: p. 31–47 (1), 48–71 (2)).
Hale, Bob & Wright, Crispin
(eds.) (2001): The Reason’s Proper Study. Essays towards a Neo-Fregean Philosophy of Mathematics . Oxford: Oxford University Press.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Hindley, J. Roger & Seldin, Jonathan P
(1986): Introduction to Combinators and λ-Calculus . Cambridge GB: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hiż, Henry
(1984): “Frege, Leśniewski and information semantics on the resolution of the antinomies.” Synthese 60 : 51–72. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Keenan, Edward L. & Faltz, Leonard M
(1985): Boolean Semantics for Natural Language . Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Lewis, David
(1986): On the Plurality of Worlds . Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Martin-Löf, Per
(1984): Intuitionistic Type Theory . Naples: Bibliopolis.Google Scholar
Meschkowski, Herbert
(1967): Probleme des Unendlichen. Werk und Leben Georg Cantors . Braunschweig: Vieweg. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Montague, Richard
(1970): “Universal grammar.” Theoria 36: 373–398. Reprinted: Thomason (1974: p. 222–246). DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(1973): “The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary English.” In: Jaakko Hintikka, Julius Moravcsik & Patrick Suppes (eds.) Approaches to Natural Language : Proceedings of the 1970 Stanford Workshop ,Dordrecht: Reidel. 221–242. Reprinted: Thomason (1974: pp. 247–270). DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Morrill, Glyn V
(1994): Type Logical Grammar. Categorial Logic of Signs . Dordrecht, Boston, London: Kluwer. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Myhill, John
(1963): “An alternative to the method of extension and intension.” In: Paul Arthur Schilpp (ed.) The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap , La Salle IL: Open Court. 299–310.Google Scholar
Nelson, David
(1949): “Constructible falsity.” The Journal of Symbolic Logic 14: 16–26. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Pierce, Benjamin
(2002): Types and Programming Languages . Cambridge MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Quine, Willard Van Orman
(1940): Mathematical Logic . Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press. Revised Edition 1951.Google Scholar
(1953): “New foundations for mathematical logic.” In: From a Logical Point of View. 9 Logico-Philosophical Essays . Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press. 80–101.Google Scholar
Ramsey, Frank P
(1927): “Facts and propositions.” Aristotelian Society Supplementary VolumeVII: 153–170. Reprinted: Ramsey, Frank P.: Foundations. Essays in Philosophy, Logic, Mathematics and Economics. Ed. by D. H.Mellor. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul 1978. 40–57.DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Robering, Klaus
(1994): “Stufen, Typen, Sorten.” In: Klaus Robering (ed.) Sorten, Typen, Typenfreiheit. Probleme der Klassifikation semantischer Einheiten ,Berlin: Technische Universität Berlin. 5–55.Google Scholar
(2000): “Categorial graph grammar: A direct approach to functor-argumentor structure.” Theoretical Linguistics 26: 31–73. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
(2008): “Ackermann’s class theory.” In: Klaus Robering (ed.) New Approaches to Classes and Concepts , London: College Publications. 23–56.Google Scholar
Scott, Dana
(1971): “The lattice of flow diagrams.” In: Erwin Engeler (ed.) Symposium on Semantics of Algorithmic Languages , Berlin, Heidelberg, New York: Springer. 311–372. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Słupecki, Jerzy
(1971): “A generalization of modal logic.” Studia Logica 28: 7–13. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Specker, Ernst P
(1953): “The axiom of choice in Quine’s ‘New Foundations for Mathematical Logic’.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 39. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Thomason, Richmond
(ed.) (1974): Formal Philosophy. Selected Papers by Richard Montague . New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
(1989): “Motivating ramified type theory.” In: Gennaro Chierchia, Barbara H. Partee & Raymond Turner (eds.) Properties, Types and Meaning. Volume I Foundational Issues , Dordrecht: Reidel. 47–62. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Villadsen, Jørgen
(2010): ∇. A Linguistic System Based on Type Theory . Berlin: LIT Verlag.Google Scholar
Wansing, Heinrich
(1993): The Logic of Information Structures . Berlin and New York: Springer. DOI logoGoogle Scholar
Whitehead, Alfred N. & Russell, Bertrand
(1910–1913): Principia Mathematica . 3 Vols. Cambridge GB: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar